Реферат

Реферат на тему Other Minds Essay Research Paper The problem

Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-13

Поможем написать учебную работу

Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.

Предоплата всего

от 25%

Подписываем

договор

Выберите тип работы:

Скидка 25% при заказе до 23.11.2024


Other Minds Essay, Research Paper

The problem of Other Minds is a true

philosophical enigma. It is apt to strike children with no philosophical

education whatsoever, yet remains intractable to many academics. Broadly

speaking, the problem can be divided into three questions. Firstly, how do

I come to believe that there are minds in the world other than my own?

Secondly, how can I justify my belief that there are minds in the world

other than my own? Thirdly, what can I state about the mental states of

minds other than my own?. The question we are dealing with here falls

largely into the third category, although of course issues relating to the

other two will also be involved.

Firstly, it is imperative to assert that, in looking for ?knowledge?, we

are not aiming for logical certainties – we are not aiming to show that

any propositions about other minds can be demonstrated with absolute

certainty equivalent to that of mathematical truths. Philosophy ever

since Descartes has tended to be defined by scepticism: either it aims to

produce sceptical theories or it aims to refute them. And sceptics tend

towards extremity in their doubts. It must be stated here and now that

there are not, and never can be, any theories that prove demonstratively

that other minds exist, or that I know others? mental states. This is not

what should be aimed at in attempting to solve the problem. As Austin puts

it “To suppose that the question ?How do I know that Tom is angry?? is

meant to mean ?How do I introspect Tom?s feelings?? is simply barking up

the wrong gum-tree.”

Most philosophers agree that their theories only bestow a greater or

lesser amount of probability onto statements about other minds (although

there are exceptions, e.g. Peter Strawson?s attempt to argue

transcendentally for the existence of other minds through our own

self-consciousness). There have been a number of different attempts to do

this. J.S. Mill, who produced the first known formulation of the Other

Minds problem, used the so-called ?Argument from Analogy? both to explain

how we come to believe in other minds and to justify this belief. Briefly,

the argument holds that I am directly aware of mental states in myself,

and I am aware of the behaviour of mine that results from and is caused by

these mental states. As I can observe similar physical behaviour in

others, I draw the analogy that it is caused by the same (or at least

similar) mental states to my own. As in all arguments from analogy, I

assume that because x is similar to y in some respects, it will be similar

in others. So as I know how I behave if I am feeling, say, angry, I assume

in someone else?s case that his behaviour is an indication of the mental

state I call ?anger?. My opinion in this respect is aided by the fact that

most humans? behaviour when they claim to be angry is broadly similar.

The argument from analogy, also employed by Bertrand Russell in a slightly

simplified form, is subject to a devastating criticism. Unlike most

analogies, in the case of other minds, there is no conceivable way of

verifying the conclusion we make. We have no way of discovering whether

someone else is angry or not, and our position means that this is a

necessary disadvantage. The only way to have someone else?s experiences

would to become that person, and in doing that, I would no longer be

myself and I would no longer be having someone else?s experiences. Thus it

is impossible to conceive of any set of experimental circumstances under

which I would be able to ascertain whether or not the human who is

expressing anger-behaviour really is angry or not. And as Norman Malcolm

has pointed out, as there are no conceivable criteria I could use to

determine whether someone is angry or not, simply claiming that they are

angry is a meaningless statement.

Many philosophers, perceiving this fatal flaw in the argument from

analogy, have attempted to produce theories on other minds that are not

based on analogy. Malcolm himself held that the problem lies in the belief

that in looking for evidence of other minds, we need to start off from our

own case and then look for evidence that other cases resemble my own in

other humans. He claimed, characteristically following Wittgenstein, that

statements about mental states in others have no ?special? status but

rather that they are ?primitive, natural expressions? of the state in

question. In other words, ‘my leg hurts’ is equivalent to non-verbal

behavioural expressions of having a painful leg such as crying, limping,

or holding my leg. The statements are not propositions as such, and so

have no ?truth-value?. In my view, there are huge problems with this

account. Firstly, its explanatory power is exceedingly limited as it makes

no distinction between those who are pretending to be in a mental state

and those who genuinely have it. How does it help us to believe that our

world is not populated by robots? Secondly, it does not sufficiently

explain how we came to attach the words we do to our mental states. Crying

and limping are ?natural?, animistic reactions to pain, but language is

learned from others. How can this be accounted for?

Other philosophers have been less successful in escaping the clutches of

the argument from analogy. H.H. Price, in his article Our Evidence for the

Existence of Other Minds, seems to dismiss it, but then employs it

himself, simply changing the terms of the analogy, claiming that we come

to believe in other minds through other humans? use of informative

language, not through their behaviour.

A.J. Ayer, in his essay One?s Knowledge of Other Minds, argues that the

belief in other minds is at least as justifiable as any other inductive

argument. When we refer to the mental states of others, the descriptive

content of that reference need not necessarily include any reference to

the possessor of that mental state. There is no contradiction in asserting

that I could have had that mental state. Implicit in this argument is

Ayer?s belief that a person is no more than the aggregate of all his

properties. Thus, as none of those properties are necessarily unavailable

to me, I make no contradiction when I say that I could have had them:

“But even if my friend has no properties which make him an exception to

the rule about feeling pain, may he not still be an exception just as

being the person that he is? And in that case how can the rest of us know

whether or not he really does feel pain? But the answer to this is that

nothing is described by his being the person that he is except the

possession of certain properties. If, per impossible, we could test for

all the properties that he possesses, and found that they did not produce

a counter-example to our general hypothesis about the conditions in which

pain is felt, our knowledge would be in this respect as good as his: there

would be nothing further left for us to discover.” (pp 213-4).

And thus, if I could have had the mental states in question, I could be

the person who had them. And if I could be that person, I could verify

whether that mental state actually exists or not. Ayer?s reasoning seems

valid enough, but it is hard to know precisely what he means. It seems

certain that in referring to mental states, it is implicit that someone

owns (or is) the mind in which those states are occurring. Although Ayer

is right in his claim that we need not refer to the ?owner? of the state

when we talk about the state itself, and therefore that the owner ?could?

be us, this doesn?t seem to address the issue at hand. The problem is one

of other minds, and we are, all of us, in a situation where we find

ourselves confronted with apparent minds other than our own which are

problematic.

>From the realisation that a belief in other minds can only arise through

observation of the behaviour of others arose the ?cul-de-sac? philosophy

of logical behaviourism. This theory, now largely discredited, holds that

all statements about mental states can be translated, without loss of

meaning, into statements about observable behaviour. Thus to say that

Jones is in pain is to say that (for instance) Jones is wincing, crying

out, grimacing etc. The statements are equivalent, and consequently the

problem of other minds is not so much solved by behaviourists as

dissolved. But the terminal problem for behaviourists lies in the case of

first-person psychological statements. We certainly don?t learn about our

own mental states by observing our own behaviour. When I say ?I have a

headache?, I don?t mean that I am clutching my head, that I am taking

aspirin etc. The feeling of the headache seems in some way to pre-empt all

of this behaviour, and generally to be the primary cause of it. The

behaviourists made a valiant attempt to solve the problem of other minds

by doing away with the asymmetry between my mental states (normally taken

to be learnt through introspection), and the mental states of others

(normally taken to be learnt through introspection), but they ultimately

failed because their account of first-person psychological statements was

utterly inadequate.

Wittgenstein, in his 1953 work Philosophical Investigations, attempted to

show that the construction of a private language (a language that no-one

other than the creator is logically capable of understanding) was

impossible because languages must follow rules, and it would be impossible

for a language with no external reference to follow rules. For instance,

if I have a certain experience x one day and call it ?pain?, and then have

another experience y the next day which happens to be different to the one

I had the day before but which seems to me identical, and so I also call

it ?pain?, how, as far a I am concerned would this situation differ from

one in which the second experience was actually x? It would not, so I

could conceivably be wrong in every statement I make regarding my own

mental states. The point Wittgenstein is trying to bring out is that,

contrary to the philosophies of Cartesianism and traditional empiricism,

the language we couch our mental statements in is a public language: the

words we use only acquire their meaning through public usage. And thus if

there were no other minds in the world other than our own, we could not

make publicly understandable statements about our mental states. This is a

powerful argument, although it is open to at least two criticisms.

Firstly, it is claimed by some philosophers that it leads inexorably to a

form of behaviourism in which my knowledge of my own mental states through

introspection is not accounted for. Secondly, the argument tells us very

little about the content of other minds. What is the relation between

words and mental states?, and more importantly, how could it conceivably

be discovered? By appeal to our own case? That would just beg the

question.

Nevertheless, I believe that Wittgenstein?s approach is the correct one.

It is a truism to say that I cannot have your experiences, and it always

remains logically possible that an malin g?nie has set me amongst a world

of unthinking, unfeeling robots who have been programmed to exhibit

behaviour (both verbal and non-verbal) leading me to assume that they have

thoughts and feelings. But this seems somewhat unlikely. Rather, it seems

more sensible to believe that there are minds animating all the beings

around me. If I am not to be subject to the sorts of criticisms that

Malcolm makes of the argument from analogy, then I must define some sort

of criteria for asserting that Mr X is feeling y etc. And my only

criteria, of course, can be my observations of his behaviour. To ensure

that my interpretations are as accurate as can be, I must take into

account everything about him: his simple overt behaviour, his environment

and social context, his biological make-up etc. And my reference point can

only be myself, as I am the only example in the world of whose mental

states I can be confident. So as far as X?s circumstances and behaviour

mirror my own, I can say that his mental states mirror mine. And I can go

slightly further: I can claim that my knowledge of my own case can give me

an idea of how certain properties and the connections between them can

affect mental states, and so if I notice some property x in X that happens

not to belong to me but of which its significance concerning mental states

I am aware, then I can make statements regarding X?s mental states with a

certain confidence. If this conclusion seems rather weak, then I can only

appeal to the enigmatic nature of the problem itself and ask others to

better it.

Finally, I would like to mention an observation of mine regarding the

nature of the problem itself. The problem of other minds arises because we

have no certain criteria for ascertaining the possessing of a mind (or

mental states) by a being, and this in turn arises because we do not know

precisely what a mind is. If philosophers of mind ever produce a theory of

mind which provides us with knowledge, to a certain extent, of the nature

of mind, then it would at least theoretically be possible to have criteria

for the possessing of mind, which would provide very good foundations for

the solving of the problem of other minds.

Bibliography

Sartre by Arthur C. Danto. Fontana, 1975.

Strawson?s Transcendental Deduction of Other Minds by J.L. Martin in New Essays in

the Philosophy of Mind ed. John-King Farlow and Roger A. Shiner. Canadian

Association for Publishing in Philosophy, 1975.

The Philosophy of Sartre by Mary Warnock. Hutchinson & co., 1965.

Analogy by Bertrand Russell in Essays on Other Minds ed. Thomas O. Buford.

University of Illinois Press, 1970.

Our Evidence for the Existence of Other Minds by H.H. Price in Essays on Other

Minds.

Wittgenstein?s Philosophical Investigations by Norman Malcolm in Essays on Other

Minds.

Knowledge of Other Minds by Norman Malcolm in Essays on Other Minds.

Other Minds by J.L. Austin in Austin?s Philosophical Papers ed. J.O. Urmson and G.J.

Warnock. Clarendon Press, 1979.

One?s Knowledge of Other Minds by A.J. Ayer in Philosophical Essays by Ayer.

Macmillan and co., 1953.

The Mind and its Place in Nature by C.D. Broad. London, 1925.

The Concept of Mind by Gilbert Ryle. London, 1949.

The Oxford Companion to Philosophy ed. Ted Honderich. Oxford, 1995.

31b


1. Реферат Основные причины кризиса
2. Реферат Маркетинговый бизнес-план
3. Курсовая Шляхи розвитку творчих здібностей дитини в процесі навчання в загальноосвітній школі
4. Реферат Экология и автомобилизация
5. Курсовая на тему Использование английских композиторов на уроках английского языка
6. Курсовая Муниципальное управление жилищно-коммунальным хозяйством
7. Реферат Иван Калита 2
8. Реферат Предмет и функции педагогики
9. Реферат на тему Белорусская культура как тип структура функции универсалии ценност
10. Курсовая на тему Иезуиты в России 1772-1820