Реферат

Реферат на тему David Hume Essay Research Paper 2

Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-14

Поможем написать учебную работу

Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.

Предоплата всего

от 25%

Подписываем

договор

Выберите тип работы:

Скидка 25% при заказе до 25.11.2024


David Hume Essay, Research Paper

"I was from the beginning scandalised, I must own, with this resemblance

between the Deity and human creatures." –Philo David Hume wrote much about

the subject of religion, much of it negative. In this paper we shall attempt to

follow Hume’s arguments against Deism as Someone knowable from the wake He

allegedly makes as He passes. This kind of Deism he lays to rest. Then, digging

deeper, we shall try our hand at a critique of his critique of religion, of

resurrecting a natural belief in God. Finally, if there’s anything Hume would

like to say as a final rejoinder, we shall let him have his last word and call

the matter closed. To allege the occurrence of order in creation, purpose in its

constituent parts and in its constituted whole, regularity in the meter of its

rhythm and syncopations, and mindful structure in the design and construction of

Nature is by far the most widely used and generally accepted ground for

launching from the world belief in an intelligent and omnipotent designer god.

One does not have to read for very long to find some modern intellectual

involved in the analysis of some part of Nature come to the "Aha!"

that there’s a power at work imposing order, design, structure and purpose in

creation. Modern religious piety salivates at the prospect of converting

scientists and will take them any way it can. From Plato to Planck the

problematic lion of religion must be rendered safe and tame. Religion must be

reasonable, after all, we are reasonable "men." Einstein writes that

the scientist’s "religious feeling takes the form of rapturous amazement at

the harmony of natural law, which reveals an intelligence of such superiority

that, compared with it, all the systematic thinking and acting of human beings

is an utterly insignificant reflection." We have been struck dumb, however;

we can no longer be incautious with such temptations to believe, with such

sirens sounding for sensible, systematic sureness. The Design Argument has been

mortally wounded by David Hume. The god arrived at by arguments on the one-way

street of effect to the cause is dead; we should never have allowed him to live.

In Section XI of the Enquiry, and throughout the Dialogues Hume subjects the

Argument from Design to searching and searing philosophical analysis, to the

point in his mind that it is forever dead, and to the point in our minds that we

wonder why the world has not yet received the obituary. Why did it not die from

the exposure to which Hume subjected it? Who resurrected this false phoenix? Has

the Design Argument been forever altered by Hume? Can it render service in

post-Hume discussions? These are the questions we should confront. David Hume’s

philosophy of religion is fatal to the natural revelation of Deism. His

arguments the camp of unbelief have appropriated. It is an argument against any

inductive proof for God’s existence. What Hume seeks to show is the failure of

this argument to establish the type of deity that belief in a particular

providence or divine action must require one to assert. This he sets out first

and in preliminary fashion in Section XI of the Enquiry and with more plethoric

attention in the Dialogues. In both books he employs the dialogue form to embody

his attacks. The argument of the former is mistitled. Fourteen of the seventeen

pages have nothing to do with immortality or "particular providence."

Hume’s argument here is from the particular effect to the existence of a cause

sufficient for its production. Causes are to be known from effects alone; to

ascribe to it any superfluous qualities goes beyond the bounds of strict logical

reasoning. The imagination must be philosophically bridled. When ten ounces are

raised in a balance one can surely surmise a counterbalance exceeding ten

ounces, but one can hardly offer any justification for the counterbalance to

weigh 100 ounces. Transferred to philosophical theology, it is impossible to

derive legitimately from a natural theology any relevancy in conclusions arrived

at over and above what can be independently and directly supported by empirical

study of the universe. Such innocuous-sounding, even camouflaged assertions by

Hume were in actuality a D-Day invasion on the Normandy Beach of the Deists. The

first salvo is a statement of the terms of reference: You then . . . have

acknowledged that the chief or sole argument for a divine existence (which I

have never questioned) is derived from the order of nature, where there appear

such marks of intelligence and design that you think it extravagant to assign

for its cause either chance or the blind and unguided force of matter. You allow

that this is an argument drawn from effects to causes. From the order of the

work you infer that there must have been project and forethought in the workman.

If you cannot make out this point you allow that your conclusion fails; and you

pretend not to establish the conclusion in a greater latitude than the phenomena

of nature will justify. The cause must be proportioned to the effect. To Hume it

is sinful to assume greater effects to an actually lesser cause. No sooner have

we engodded the gods with power and intelligence and benevolence than we summon

"exaggeration and flattery" to supply gaps and tease out the argument.

We structure an entire edifice in our imaginations while standing on the porch.

Hume countered this thinking because it constructed belief and certainty out of

mere possibility. It is an exercise in uselessness: "Because our knowledge

of this cause being derived entirely from the course of nature, we can never,

according to the rules of just reasoning, return back from the cause with any

new inference, or making additions to the common and experienced course of

nature, establish any new principles of conduct and behaviour." Experience

must be the true guide for philosopher and deist. The experiencing one can never

be held hostage to those armed with theory or conjecture about the nature of

Reality. Also, the experiencing one must be careful not to compromise her

experience by inflating it with false conclusions which do not fit the close

tolerances of experience. "Why torture your brain to justify the course of

nature upon suppositions, which, for aught you know, may be entirely imaginary,

and of which there are to be found no traces in the course of nature?"

Then, Hume raises an objection. If experience is our only and final interlocutor

and arbiter, why can one not use one’s experience and say that a half-finished

building, surrounded by all the materials and tools necessary for its

completion, will be one day complete? Or, cannot Robinson Crusoe, seeing one

human footprint on the shore, conclude he is not alone? This objection he

answers through his dialogue partner: There is an infinite difference between

the human and the divine. With humans one can infer from effect to cause and

then infer anew concerning the effect because we have other corroborating

experience about humans, from motives to operations. Our inferences about

probabilities in human nature and works can be experienced. Not so with the

divine, who is single, suigeneris, neither empirically obvious nor predictable.

We have no experience to arbitrate here, there is no existing genus of thought.

Conjecture must be arbitrary. To insist the deity is known from design is to

substitute ourselves and our experience for the deity, and then to assume this

Agent will act as we would. This is speculation, and Hume allows it no

authority. "We can never be allowed to mount up from the universe, the

effect, to Jupiter, the cause, and then descend downward to infer any new effect

from that cause .. The knowledge of the cause being derived solely from the

effect, they must be exactly adjusted to each other; and the one can never refer

to anything further or be the foundation of any new inference and

conclusion." If Hume is right the implications are far-reaching. The first

is embarrassing to those who wield natural proofs of God: we still have no idea

or knowledge from these proofs what this God does, what the deity values, what

It rewards and what It punishes. We cannot in any sense of logic speak of the

deity’s possible or probable attributes or actions. Such a class of topics Hume

renders unwarranted. An invalid argument will not support a conclusion, not

partially, not even weakly. It supports it not at all. Hume repeats and

amplifies his voice in the Dialogues with the help of three protagonists,

Cleanthes, Philo and Demea. Debate still rages on whether Cleanthes or Philo

most faithfully represents Hume. No one character fully presents the force of

Hume’s arguments; his beliefs are on the tongues of all three. Hume’s purpose is

to vitiate the Argument from Design more completely, and to this end he

skillfully balances his words among the protagonists; to let the currency of his

argument fall upon the shoulders of one person alone would not only destroy the

Dialogue by definition, but would also diminish that dramatic interest in it

which also constitutes its value. Philo begins the engagement of the problem of

natural religion: [W]hen we look beyond human affairs and the properties of the

surrounding bodies: When we carry our speculations into the two eternities,

before and after the present state of things; into the creation and formation of

the universe; the existence and properties of spirits; the powers and operations

of one universal spirit, existing without beginning and without end; omnipotent,

omniscient, immutable, infinite, and incomprehensible: We must be far removed

from the smallest tendency to skepticism not to be apprehensive, that we have

here got quite beyond the reach of our faculties. So long as we confine our

speculations to trade, or morals, or politics, or criticism, we make appeals,

every moment, to common sense and experience, which strengthen our philosophical

conclusions, and remove (at least, in part) the suspicion, which we so justly

entertain with regard to every reasoning that is very sub tile and refined. But

in theological reasoning’s, we have not this advantage; while at the same time

we are employed upon object . . . too large for our grasp. . . . We are like

foreigners in a strange country, to whom every thing must seem suspicious, and

who are in danger every moment of transgressing against the laws and customs of

the people with whom they live and converse. We know not how far we ought to

trust our vulgar methods of reasoning in such a subject; since, even in common

life and in that province which is peculiarly appropriated to them, we cannot

account for them, and are entirely guided by a kind of instinct or necessity in

employing them. Philosophically, the argument is cast thus: is religion to be

the extension of principles and ideas implicit in daily knowledge of the world?

For Cleanthes early on, the purveyor of common sense, religious hypotheses, like

scientific ones, are founded on the "simplest and most obvious

arguments," and unless it meets with artificial obstacles, has "easy

access and admission into the mind of man." Philo maintains his skeptic’s

silence until later in the Dialogues, and speak only to facilitate honest

inquiry. In Part II, Cleanthes is drawn out by Philo and by his own growing

self-confidence to assert that what is true for religious hypotheses also rings

true for claims about the nature of God. Cleanthes is led beyond the areas he

was able to hold within practical reasoning into areas where he is vulnerable to

the applications of his own reasoning. Ordinary experience, he claims, can

settle the question of God: Look around the world: Contemplate the whole and

every part of it: You will find it to be nothing but one great machine,

subdivided into an infinite number of lesser machines…. All these various

machines … are adjusted to each other with an accuracy, which vanishes into

admiration all men who have ever contemplated them…. We are led to infer …

that the Author of nature is somewhat similar to the mind of man; though

possessed of much larger faculties, proportional to the grandeur of the work

which he has executed. By this argument a posteriori, and by this argument

alone, we do prove at once the existence of a Deity, and his similarity to human

mind and intelligence. Yet this inadequate analogy of Cleanthes falls short.

Inferring from the world order to the nature of God, from humanity writ large,

does not support the religious piety and philosophic rationales about the nature

of God. Philo slices this argument with the sword of constant conjunction.

Constant conjunction among events may explain those sequences that are often

observed, but it cannot deliver the answer to the question of the world’s

origin: we cannot observe or experience it. By the end of Part III Cleanthes has

spent his common sense arguments and returns to the background; though he often

speaks, his breaking of his silence breaks no new ground. Philo expounds his

arguments further, culminating in this riposte to Cleanthes: Your theory itself

cannot surely pretend to any such advantage; even though you have run into

anthropomorphism, the better to preserve a conformity to common experience. Let

us once more put it to trial. In all instances which we have ever seen, ideas

are copied from real objects, and are ectypal, not archetypal, to express myself

in learned terms: You reverse this order, and give thought the precedence. In

all instances which we have ever seen, though has no influence upon matter,

except that matter is so conjoined with it, as to have an equal reciprocal

influence upon it. Cleanthes makes no substantial reply, and Demea the pietist

comes to the stage with another set of conditions with which the Argument from

Design must be reconciled. These conditions include the unhappiness of humanity

and human corruption. With his famous ejaculation, "The whole earth,

believe me Philo, is cursed and polluted," he sounds the note Philo has

been waiting to hear to drown out Cleanthes’ flat pitch. He queries Cleanthes

how, in the face of the orchestrated facts, can he assert the "moral

attributes of the Deity, his justice, benevolence, mercy, and rectitude, to be

of the same nature with these virtues in the human creature? His power we allow

infinite: Whatever he wills is executed: But neither man nor animal are happy .

. . . In what respect, then, do his benevolence and mercy resemble the

benevolence and mercy of men?" With these words, Philo proceeds al fine,

allegro non stoppo, championing his cause. His reasoning dampens any spark of

hope for whatever good there may be in Nature. Here he understands Nature as

something in which nothing can be regarded as essential, and nothing if anything

can be taken as temptation for one to covet a higher state of living and

experience. Note the contrasts of his analogy with Cleanthes’ earlier machine:

Look round this universe. What an immense profusion of beings, animated and

organized, sensible and active! You admire this prodigious variety and

fecundity. But inspect a little more narrowly these living existences, the only

beings worth regarding. How hostile and destructive to each other! How

insufficient all of them for their own happiness! How contemptible and odious to

the spectator! The whole presents nothing but the idea of a blind nature,

impregnated by a great vivifying principle, and pouring forth from her lap,

without discernment or parental care, her maimed and abortive children! The true

conclusion for Philo is that the original source of every thing is wholly

apathetic to all the principles at work in the universe, and regards health no

better than harm, good not better than evil, lightness no better than heaviness.

Nature is a mixed, balkanized state. And so the coup de grace: If one is baffled

about the true state of the world, how can one argue from design? Rather than

following Demea out the door, however, Cleanthes converts. The Dialogues,

however, does not commit the error of tendering Philo’s view as the correct one.

Cleanthes’ conversion demonstrates it is enough for the view to be credible. In

one sense, irrespective of the demolition of the Argument from Design, or the

"religious hypothesis", the Dialogues is a dramatization of the

success and achievement of skepticism. It is a concession of the inadequacy of

every weltbild to present itself as the norm. Philo (read Hume) uses his

skepticism to balance theory against theory and so suspend judgment. The one who

is able to balance theory off theory, holding none of one’s own, is the victor.

So skepticism is the rationalists’ arrow to skewer natural theology. It

therefore appears every endeavor to argue from design, like the Promised Land,

has its Dead Sea. Arguments may float, but desiccated by the salt and sun of

skepticism, will hold no convincing power. They are in principle impossible. A

priori questions must be asked: what is the bias of the world view? Views of

nature are fashioned from concealed (even from the fashioner) bias by the one(s)

who fashion them. What Cleanthes says about Nature and God says more about

Cleanthes than Nature and God. By postulating predictive impotence, Hume has set

up an impasse. The death knell of Hume’s refutation of natural theology has left

undaunted some critics of his writings. It has proven to be a tarbaby to all who

are bound by the same questions as Hume about natural theology. To be a

successful, enduring critic of Hume one has to change the nature of the

Question, or, introduce new categories of thinking, questions and categories to

which Hume might not have enjoyed access. 1. R.G. Swinburne maintained that no

criticism of Hume against natural theology has any validity against a more

"carefully articulated version of the argument." Employing arguments

of analogy based not on spatial but on temporal regularities, Swinburne has

satisfied himself that he has shown the Design Argument to be a legitimate

inference to the best explanation for God. Its value depends only upon the vigor

and durability of the analogy and upon the degree to which the resulting theory

makes explanations more simple and coherent. Moreover, in the Design Argument he

thinks strengthens the Christian monotheism habit. Swinburne launches his new

and improved version of the Design Argument by nuancing the types of order into

spatial and temporal categories. An example of the former is a section of books

on a library shelf arranged by author’s last name in alphabetical order. The way

bodies behave in accordance to the law of gravitation illustrates the latter.

Keeping a mental finger on this, he then hypothesizes that in order to explain

the operation of many natural laws, we should lay them at the feet of divine

activity; they are not scientifically or empirically obvious. With this

established, he then proves how an analogical argument can be designed to show

how evidence confirms the hypothesis. As are caused by Bs. A*s are similar to

As. Therefore–given that there is no more satisfactory explanation of the

existence of A*s–they are produced by B*s similar to Bs. B*s are postulated to

be similar in all respects to Bs except in so far as shown otherwise, viz.,

except in so far as the dissimilarities between As and A*s force us to postulate

a difference. In the Design Argument, As are regularities of succession, Bs are

the human agents who cause As. A*s are the regularities of succession

exemplified by natural laws and B*s are the rational agents or causes of A*s of

divine status. Like humans (As), A*s can be somewhat favorably compared to

humans in terms of free choice and intelligence. The difference is in degree,

not kind. The result is a Design Argument, and if true, is conditional upon the

strength of the analogy and upon how coherent empirical matters are processed to

a divine cause. 2. A second objection centers in the critique of constant

conjunction. Is one instance in itself of constant conjunction sufficient to

know a cause from inspection to its effect? In the Treatise Hume has urged us to

conceive of events occurring without any causes at all; anything may be the

cause of anything. How do these implicate his Argument from Design? Are our

observations one-on-one with our experiences? Is the constant conjunction of

events, which Hume says must be experienced as cause and effect, the only

legitimate permission we possess for inferring either from the presence of the

other? Why can we not infer from the simple and unparalleled fact of the

universe an equally simple and unparalleled Deity as Cause? 3. A final objection

comes from science. Every scientific stride has come from its putting forth

hypotheses which extend beyond the phenomena observed. A scientific theory that

proceeded only upon existing data would be worthless. It could not as an

explanation guide experiments and research. Scientists must venture out beyond

the already known and infer the unknown. And so do we. We look at our children,

grandchildren, brothers, sisters and parents and infer heredity, or more

specifically, genes. DNA is an unostentatious reality, inexperienced, but we see

its effect. Can we not legitimately infer God as a way to account and even

foretell phenomena of the universe? Hume replies: Ok, OK, so I was not as

careful as I might have been in formulating my principle that on the other side

of experience there is no door leading to conjecture or hypothesis. I have

expressed myself badly in places, but I think I can salvage my cause with a more

circumspect exposition. Mr. Swinburne, my respects. You have scored a good

point. But your chessboard of an analogy fails because you are too ready to

ascribe natural laws to a Deity, when they are pawns unequal to the task of

checkmating the prize piece. Natural Laws are not empirically obvious: there is

your mistake. When inferring any particular cause, given certain effects, one

cannot ascribe any qualities but what are sufficient to explain adequately the

cause. "Adequately" is the watchword. The explanation should be kept

as simple as possible. It is unscientific to ascribe certain characteristics to

a postulated designer of the universe if those characteristics go beyond what is

required adequately to explain the facts. And this god of yours, Mr. Swinburne,

whence came He? Is not your God subject to creation–a cause–Himself? I lay

your argument to rest at the feet of infinite regression. As to this second

objection. You have divorced your arguments from the authoritative range of

experience. My argument is not contained within that old wine skin of analogy.

When we face a new species of phenomena, our observation and experience prove

unequal to the task; and analogy will fail as a way of explanation as well. As

an argument from analogy the Argument from Design is on serviceable. No matter

what I’ve said elsewhere, experience leads me only to one honest conclusion:

While others take their broad-jump leaps of faith and land in the quicksand of

subjective conjecture, I stand on the rock of experience. Have you experienced

the universe as a simple and unparalleled fact? Have you faced a new species of

suigeneris phenomena? If you have, then you must truly be God! Of course things

will happen without a ready Cause, but that affords you no permission to assign

divine causes left and right, willy-nilly, and certainly no license to worship

this divinity. Now to the third argument. As some are fond of saying, "Your

god is too small." You take one realm of localized phenomena, and without

benefit of experience, you analogize a God. In science, how many false

hypotheses do you come up with before you arrive at a true one? Are you willing

to constitute a religion and call people to faith based on what might be a false

hypothesis? What happens when you find two true but conflicting hypotheses, as

we have with the nature of light? Is it a particle or a wave? As for the DNA

model of analogy, it won’t reward you with a larger version or vision of the god

of DNA. Analogies are inductive. Inductions, we have proven over and over, are

not sufficient grounds for the certainty you would require. Induction can only

give you a probability, and I’d like to see you preach a probability! Ha Ha. All

these slippery objections, specific textual questions and ever-more refined

points of logic are nothing but a series of assurances that you can never put

one over on me. All reasoning, all inquiries into the nature of the Deity, rests

on custom and habit. There is no rational foundation for your claims of

"fact." Your measures and claims of fact are not knowledge, objective

and verifiable, but beliefs. You cannot make causal claims of fact when

causation itself is suspect because of necessary connection. Your Design

Arguments are arrested at the very outset at the roadblock of a category

mistake. One cannot synthesize from the parts a whole that has nothing to do

with the parts themselves. This is the mental gymnastics of a finite mind, and

the finite cannot re-present the unknowable infinite. The finite has no

metaphysical license to trespass its boundaries. If you do, the best you can do

is bag unicorns and dragons; the worst you could do is to divinize your

passions, lusts, cruelties, vengeance and the most heinous of vices. All your

religious systems are subject to great and insuperable difficulties. Each will

have its day, expose itself, and die from exposure. But all of them prepare a

complete triumph for the skeptic, who reminds over and over that no system can

be embraced without some troublesome remainder. A total suspension of judgment

is my only refuge, my mighty fortress. It is the only sanctuary I don’t have to

defend. The purpose of my open mind regarding uncertainty is to close it on this

one thing certain: That the Cause (or Causes) of order in the universe bear no

remote resemblance or analogy to humans, animals, plants or nature. What that is

we can’t know, for it is parasitic on data we shall never be able to

interrogate.


1. Реферат на тему Great Gatsby Essay Research Paper The characters
2. Реферат Использование криминалистических средств и методов в установлении лица совершившего
3. Реферат на тему Never Cry Wolf Essay Research Paper In
4. Реферат на тему Управленческий учет и ценообразование
5. Доклад на тему Анна Ахматова
6. Курсовая Общественное разделение труда и развитие общественного характера производства
7. Реферат Разработка нормативной документации на фирменное блюдо слоеное желе Малинки
8. Реферат Компании долгожители России. Кондитерская фабрика Красный Октябрь
9. Контрольная работа Философская система мировоззрения Социальное неравенство и социальная стратификация
10. Реферат Угрюмов, Григорий Иванович