Реферат

Реферат на тему Aristotle Vs Plato

Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-14

Поможем написать учебную работу

Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.

Предоплата всего

от 25%

Подписываем

договор

Выберите тип работы:

Скидка 25% при заказе до 22.11.2024


Aristotle Vs. Plato’s Theory Of Ideas Essay, Research Paper

Aristotle refutes Plato’s Theory of Ideas on three basic grounds: that

the existence of Ideas contradicts itself by denying the possibility of

negations; that his illustrations of Ideas are merely empty metaphors; and that

they theory uses impermanent abstractions to create examples of perception.

Though the theory is meant to establish concrete standards for the knowledge of

reality, Aristotle considers it fraught with inconsistencies and believes that

the concept of reality depends upon all forms’ correlations to other elements.

Ideas, Plato believes, are permanent, self-contained absolutes, which answered

to each item of exact knowledge attained through human thought. Also, Ideas are

in Plato’s view concrete standards by which all human endeavor can be judged,

for the hierarchy of all ideas leads to the highest absolute – that of Good. In

addition, the theory claims that states of being are contingent upon the

mingling of various Forms of existence, that knowledge is objective and thus

clearly more real, and that only the processes of nature were valid entities.

However, Aristotle attacks this theory on the grounds that Plato’s arguments are

inconclusive either his assertions are not al all cogent. Aristotle says, or his

arguments lead to contradictory conclusions. For example, Aristotle claims that

Plato’s arguments lead one to conclude that entities (such as anything man-made)

and negations of concrete ideas could exist – such as "non-good" in

opposition to good. This contradicts Plato’s own belief that only natural

objects could serve as standards of knowledge. Also, Aristotle refutes Plato’s

belief that Ideas are perfect entities unto themselves, independent of

subjective human experience. Ideas, Aristotle claims, are not abstractions on a

proverbial pedestal but mere duplicates of things witnessed in ordinary daily

life. The Ideas of things, he says, are not inherent to the objects in

particular but created separately and placed apart from the objects themselves.

Thus, Aristotle says, Plato’s idea that Ideas are perfect entities, intangible

to subjective human experience, is meaningless, for all standards are based

somewhere in ordinary human activity and perception. Thirdly, Aristotle assails

Plato’s efforts to find something common to several similar objects at once, a

perfect exemplar of the quality those things share. Beauty is a perfect example;

Plato considered Beauty both a notion and an ideal, isolated by abstractions and

fixed permanently while its representatives fade away. Aristotle claims that

abstractions like Beauty cannot be cast as absolutes, independent of temporal

human experience; the Idea of Beauty changes with time and individual

perceptions and cannot (as Plato felt) exist forever as a concrete standard.

Plato and Aristotle reach some agreement, though, on the topic of reality. Plato

believes that all reality was derived from his Ideas (which themselves dealt

with concrete hierarchy of rational ideas. St. Anselm, though, makes the most

dogmatic and logically tortuous case for God’s existence, relying not upon

explanations of goodness, truth, or rational order of ideas but upon an absurd

argument. He claims that everyone has some sense of God, and he claims that for

one to deny God’s existence is an invalid and contradictory assertion;

therefore, God exists. Also, Anselm believes that those capable of understanding

God cannot believe that he does not exist – as if the enormity of the idea was

so clear than only a fool could not perceive it. His arguments seem the weakest

of the four viewpoints here, for they are riddled with dogma and assume that God

is a constant – using faith alone. Anselm considers faith paramount to logic or

other forms of thought and asks no questions as to what powers the universe or

what goodness is – he basically follows the Christian "party line" too

closely to be valid. In general, St. Augustine combines Plato’s idea of a moral

hierarchy with his own rational observations of truth and goodness being

embodied in their highest form by God. While Plato wavers on God’s superiority,

Aristotle views man as god’s pawn, and Anselm uses tortuous dogmatic logic,

Augustine’s arguments seem to make the most sense from not only a Christian

point of view but from a moral and rational one as well. The philosophies of

Plato, Aristotle, St. Augustine, and St. Anselm on the existence of God all vary

on the issue of God’s nature; though each thinker takes a different approach to

why there is a God, that of St. Augustine seems the most valid because he takes

a rational stance and does not dogmatically assume God’s existence. Plato’s

philosophy assumes that God exists as a supremely good being whose goodness is

analogous to Plato’s concrete concept or the ultimate good. However, God and

goodness are not one and the same; Plato does not directly state that goodness

is good, but that God is good, since he exemplifies the idea at the top of

Plato’s hierarchy. In short, God does not equal goodness, but God encompasses it

better than any other being. This implies not that God is perfect, but that

God’s intentions and actions have good aims – goodness may emerge from other

sources besides God. The main problem with Plato’s philosophy is his

inconsistency; he owes the existence of his Ideas to both God and goodness, but

he claims the two are not identical. God becomes subordinate to the

"universals" in Plato’s ordered cosmos, and his defense of God appears

rather weak. While Plato assumes God exists as the ultimately good (but not

omnipotent) being, Aristotle questions God’s active role in the universe and

claims that nature depends upon an immaterial Supreme Being. For example, he

cites natural genesis and the perpetuity of movement as evidence of God’s

immaterial existence, and he implies that God is a self-sufficient, compelling

force for both nature and man. Aristotle’s concept of God seems valid as a

pre-scientific explanation of the universe; however, he seems to ignore God’s

embodiment of moral goodness and man’s ability to think and act freely and still

be good. He believes that all goodness comes from within God and that the

goodness in man is drawn toward God and nothing else. Aristotle’s ideas on God

seem, from a modern point of view, effective only as explanations of the

supernatural and even of the miracle of life. St. Augustine links God with

rational thought and states that human knowledge of truth depends upon man’s

relationship to God. His argument moves him from existence of the self to the

objectivity of truth and finally to God’s reality. Augustine assumes that God is

a rational being and that the rational and the good are identical. Only God

could be superior to truth, he says, and therefore must be the ultimate good;

therefore, truth, goodness, and God are one and the same. His argument seems

fairly clear-eyed and rational, for he does not approach God’s goodness

dogmatically or automatically assume God’s existence. Instead, he works toward

that end by evaluation the rationality of truth and goodness, and he casts God

in that role as the ultimate embodiment of both. In general, Augustine implies,

God represents goodness and occupies the pinnacle of the concept like unity and

twoness). He considers unity and goodness the combined center of his system of

Ideas and stated that the Ideas had to be more real and concrete than any

objects of ordinary experience. Aristotle, meanwhile, agreed with Plato’s notion

that the immaterial (form) and the material (matter) were distinctly separate

entities; however, he did not share Plato’s belief that all forms were

permanent, freestanding truths; he felt that form correlated to matter. Ideas,

he stated, correlated to something material and were thus changeable and often

dependent upon the observer. In general, Aristotle refutes Plato on the grounds

that his Theory of Ideas tries too hard to establish concrete, universal

definitions for things that depend too much on the material. Though both

thinkers agree on the separation of the material and immaterial (which gave both

a somewhat similar view of God), they still differ sharply over the permanence

of standards by which human nature and endeavor can be judged.


1. Диплом Специализированная поликлиника в г Краснодаре
2. Реферат на тему Euthanasia Should Doctor-Assisted Suicide Be Lagalized
3. Реферат Ду Юэшэн
4. Курсовая на тему Российский рынок корпоративных ценных бумаг
5. Реферат Определение общения
6. Реферат на тему CrossCultural Communication Barriers Essay Research Paper BUSN
7. Статья на тему Кинематика вращения
8. Курсовая Поверочный тепловой расчет парового котла Е-420-138-560 ТП-81 на сжигание Назаровского бурого
9. Доклад на тему Февральская революция
10. Сочинение на тему Ахматова а. - звезды смерти стояли нал нами...