Реферат на тему Antigone And Creon Essay Research Paper Many
Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-03Поможем написать учебную работу
Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.
Antigone And Creon Essay, Research Paper
Many dramatic theorists have documented their opinions of Sophocles’ tragic play
Antigone. They have presented their interpretations as to the motives and moral
character of Antigone and Creon. I will attempt to encapsulate the basic logic behind the
arguments of the critics Brian Vickers, A.C. Bradley (who interprets Hegel), and H. D. F.
Kitto, and venture my own humble opinion as to their validity.
Brian Vickers clearly favors the character of Antigone. He challenges Hegel and
Hegel’s view that both Creon and Antigone were essentially right in their beliefs. Vickers
sums up Hegel’s theories in a single diagram (Vickers 526), showing Creon and Antigone
as forces in antithetical opposition. I believe that Hegel’s theories of tragedy, as explained
by A.C. Bradley, encompass much more than a simple diagram. Hegel thought that Creon
and Antigone represented these forces, but not necessarily that they were diametrically
opposed. Hegel thought that the tragedy of Antigone was that the beliefs of Antigone and
Creon forced them into opposition, because their beliefs were valid and just, though they
did not go about practicing their beliefs in a valid and just manner.
Vickers presents the notion that Sophocles himself favored the character of
Antigone, since Sophocles never criticized her. With this I must disagree; there were
many aspects of Antigone’s character that Sophocles would not have included had he
viewed her as above reproach. For instance, she is dreadfully overbearing and righteous.
While Sophocles clearly showed he could paint the picture of a sympathetic character if
he so chose in Oedipus the King, I believe that he deliberately made Antigone, frankly, a
much more bitchy character than Oedipus.
Oedipus displays sympathy and is emotive in ways that Antigone simply isn’t, and
that makes Oedipus the King much more tragic than Antigone. Here, Oedipus
demonstrates his compassionate nature when he tells the plague-stricken citizens of
Thebes how he feels for their distress (Sophocles 48):
Poor children! You may be sure I know
All that you longed for in your coming here.
I know that you are deathly sick; and yet,
Sick as you are, not one is as sick as I.
Each of you suffers in himself alone
His anguish, not another’s; but my spirit
Groans for the city, for myself, for you.
Oedipus will not be deterred in his search for the truth, no matter who tries to
persuade him to abandon the quest (Sophocles 64):
Oedipus: Do you know anything about him, Lady? Is he the man
we summoned? Is that the man this shepherd means?
Jocasta: Why think of him? Forget this herdsman. Forget it
all. This talk is a waste of time.
Oedipus: How can you say that, when the clues to my birth are
in my hands?
Jocasta: For God’s love, let us have no more questioning! Is
your life nothing to you? My own is pain enough for
me to bear.
Oedipus: You need not worry. Suppose my mother a slave, and
born of slaves: no baseness can touch you.
Jocasta: Listen to me, I beg you: do not do this thing!
Oedipus: I will not listen; the truth must be made known.
Oedipus’ conscious choice to pursue and accept his doom makes him a tragic
figure. Bernard M. W. Knox, author of The Heroic Temper: Studies in Sophoclean
Tragedy, points out that the hero has to choose between his doom and an alternative
“which if accepted would betray the hero’s own conception of himself, his rights, his
duties,” but in the end the hero “refuses to yield; he remains true to himself, to his physis,
that ‘nature’ which he inherited from his parents and which is his identity.” (Knox 106)
Therefore, one can see Oedipus’s unwavering insistence to uncover the truth about the
murder of Laius, and then about himself, as proof of the hero’s resolute commitment to
uphold his own nature. Oedipus’ unyielding quest for the truth fits his self image as a man
of action, the revealer of truth, and the solver of riddles. Knox adds that the hero’s
determination to act is “always announced in emphatic, uncompromising terms.” (Knox
22). Oedipus proclaims his intention of finding Laius’ killers by saying, “Then once more
I must bring what is dark to light.” (Sophocles 49).
The hero cannot be swayed by threats nor reason; he will not capitulate.
Creon, after being accused by Oedipus of conspiring against the king, retorted, “You do
wrong when you take good men for bad, bad men for good. . . . In time you will know
this well.” (Sophocles 58). Oedipus, however, never learns in time; he remains
unchanged.
Oedipus, after his terrible self-mutilation, realizes that he treated Creon unjustly:
“Alas, how can I speak to him? What right have I to beg his courtesy whom I deeply
wronged?” (Sophocles 70). But later, Creon has to remind Oedipus that he is no longer
king when he starts issuing imperious commands such as: “But let me go, Creon!”; “Take
pity on them; see, they are only children, friendless except for you.”; “Promise me this,
Great Prince, and give me your hand in token of it.”; “No! Do not take them from me!”
(Sophocles 71).
The hero provided the ancient Greeks the belief that in some chosen person
“humanity is capable of superhuman greatness . . . that a human being may at times
magnificently defy the limits imposed on our will by the fear of public opinion, of
community action, even of death, may refuse to accept humiliation and indifference and
impose his will no matter what the consequences to others and to himself.” (Knox 60).
This unyielding resolve to accept his doom, “no matter what the consequences to others
and to himself,” to bestow meaning to his life, gives the hero “a dignity, a nobility, and a
grandeur that do not tarnish with the passage of time. When he is most vulnerable, he is
most noble.” (Knox 60).
Antigone, meanwhile, has a certain dignity and nobility as well, but lacks the
emotional punch of Oedipus because she doesn’t care how her circumstances and
decisions affect others. She would feel hatred toward even a loved one who tried to stop
her (Sophocles/Jebb pars. 29-30):
Ismene: A hopeless quest should not be made at all.
Antigone: If thus thou speakest, thou wilt have hatred from me, and will justly be subject to the lasting hatred of the dead.
Antigone has one line which irks me in particular. After being discovered while
burying her brother’s body for the second time, Antigone is confronted by Creon, who
reasons that “A foe is never a friend–not even in death.” To this, Antigone responds,”Tis
not my nature to join in hating, but in loving.” (Sophocles/Jebb pars. 116-117). This
seems like an outright lie, something that a more tragic figure like Oedipus would never
utter. Antigone certainly demonstrates her nature to hate, when she condemns her sister
even as Ismene shows Antigone love (Sophocles/Jebb pars. 123-126):
Ismene: But now that ill besets thee, I am not ashamed to sail the sea of trouble at thy side.
Antigone: Whose was the deed, Hades and the dead are witnesses:
a friend in word is not the friend that I love.
Ismene: And what life is dear to me, bereft of thee?
Antigone: Ask Creon; all they care is for him.
Vickers says that Creon was “lawful” in decreeing that Polyneices not be buried,
but this is the only issue that Creon is “right” about. He believes that Creon is “repugnant”
to the reader, because Creon “gloats over the future fate of the corpse.” (Vickers 528). I
must disagree again. Creon was never repugnant to me personally. Had I been in his
position, and a nephew of mine committed treason against my kingdom and killed my
second nephew, I would have done much the same thing: let his corpse rot and be
consumed by scavengers. Neither would being challenged by a willful, bratty child bring
out my compassionate, loving side.
Antigone feels a duty and a necessity to bury her brother Polyneices, but rarely
does she mention any kind of suffering or loss. She seems concerned only with doing
the righteous thing. Meanwhile, Creon makes his decree out of passion and anger, and
that makes him more human to me than Antigone could ever be. Antigone becomes
distraught over her brother only when she discovers that he has ben re-buried, and it
seems that her distress springs from her actions being undone; the fact that that action is
burying Polyneices is only a coincidence.
Vickers believes that Creon has a “sadistic enjoyment of his brutality,” (Vickers
531) such as when Creon challenges the guard who reports that Polyneices has been
buried and threatens that guard with death if he does not uncover the culprit. I don’t see
Creon as enjoying his threats here. I believe that he is furious at being disobeyed. He is
enraged that someone cannot see things the way he does: a traitor’s body should receive
no special treatment. Vickers also says that Creon is especially angry at being challenged
by a woman; to this, I say: so what? The traditional role of women in ancient Greek
society, aside from the polis of Sparta which was the exception, was to stay indoors and
raise children. It stands to reason that Creon would indeed be angrier at being opposed by
Antigone, whose mission in life seems to be instigation anyway.
I can definitely relate more closely to H.D.F. Kitto’s interpretation of the play.
Kitto believes that Creon is the main character, and that Sophocles deliberately portrays
him as such. Creon has more dramatic forces deployed against him than Antigone, who
only has to face Creon’s wrath. Creon’s tragedy grows before our very eyes, while
Antigone’s doom is “forseen and swift.” (Kitto 127). The real conflict of the play,
according to Kitto, is the gods against Creon.
Unfortunately, Kitto goes on to say that Hegel’s view of Antigone is
“preposterous.” Hegel says that something is “seriously wrong” with Antigone, while
Kitto counters with the statement that “only Hegel can tell us” what Antigone’s “blemish”
is (Kitto 129). I have to agree with Hegel here. Antigone takes a principle, valid or not,
and rams it down everyone’s throat with her words and deeds. She is a glory hound and a
would-be martyr. She does not need to announce her deed, or be caught doing it; she
chooses this course of action. She invades a camp of guards and manages to bury a body
and leave no tracks. She surely must know that the body will be uncovered at some point,
so why does she not consider her duty done after the first burial? Or, since she is so adept
at sneaking around, why not remove the body and bury it somewhere it will never be
discovered? Did she intend to check the body every day to make sure it was still buried?
Her actions are nonsensical and illogical unless they are specifically engineered to say,
“Here I am, the only one doing the right thing, so punish me! I am better than all of you!”
There in no loyalty to her brother in her behavior.
On to Hegel: Macbeth is as “far removed” as possible from Antigone, but is still
“of one nature” (Bradley 89) with it. The death of Macbeth is much less tragic than
Antigone, because Macbeth wasn’t essentially a good man. Antigone was following the
edicts of the gods in burying her brother and was doing rightly as far as she knew. I
would agree that Macbeth’s death is less tragic, yet I feel worse for him than I do for
Antigone. At least Macbeth was an emotive, passionate man, not a righteous machine.
Hegel believes that all other things in tragedies being equal, the tragedy with the
hero as a good man is more tragic than as a bad. The more spiritual value, i.e. Antigone
doing her deed for spiritual purposes, the more tragedy in conflict and waste. The more
evil a character, the less tragic his circumstances. Moral evil diminishes the spiritual
value of personality.
Because Antigone and Creon are trying to do what they feel is right at heart, their
conflict has much stronger implications than the conflicts in MacBeth, since MacBeth
was a murderer who wanted to ascend to the throne. Which is not to say that MacBeth
isn’t a tragedy, because it is much more than just a conflict between good and evil.
Hegel believes that ethical or universal ends and justice have nothing to do with
catastrophe. A tragic action is a self-division, or internal conflict, and the catastrophe is
the annulment of this division, but this is only half of Hegel’s ideas.
A catastrophe has two aspects, negative and affirmative. It is a power which is
irresistible and inescapable, and negates anything incompatible with it. But if a
catastrophe were only such an unintelligent, characterless force, it would invoke feelings
of horror, with is not a feeling associated with tragedy (like pity and fear). It is also the
source of our feelings of reconciliation. The catastrophe is the violent restitution of the
divided spiritual unity, and some sort of projection of the division in the hero. So that
there is some sort of paradoxical feeling in the inevitable death of the hero, when we die
with him, yet exult or feel that his death means nothing. The hero escapes the power
which killed him.
Of the three critics and theorists, I relate to Hegel the most. He knows that
Antigone and Creon are flawed beings, though they do what they feel is morally right. He
realizes that they take their morality and let it become their personalities and define their
actions, instead of just influencing them. And therefore, though worthy of sympathy, they
are the masters of their fates, and choose their respective dooms.
Hegel believed that the tragedy of Antigone lies in the conflict between the
rules of the state and the rules of man. It is unfortunate that these two forces must be in
opposition, and therefore their practitioners or champions in this particular case have to
be in opposition as well. I agree with this; the tragedy is in the circumstances that pit two
essentially “right” forces against each other. The morality of the characters determines
the course of the tragedy, and their personalities and convictions determine the emotional
power for the reader.
Bibliography
Vickers, Brian. Towards Greek Tragedy: Drama, Myth, Society
Bradley, AC. Oxford Lectures on Poetry
Kitto, HDF. Greek Tragedy, A Literary Study
4. Knox, Bernard MW. The Heroic Temper: Studies in Sophoclean Tragedy
Sophocles. “Oedipus the King”
Sophocles. “Antigone”