Реферат на тему UnH1d Essay Research Paper Let us suppose
Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-18Поможем написать учебную работу
Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.
Untitled Essay, Research Paper
Let us suppose that killing as a form of punishment is a moral and universally
accepted practice. Would it then be acceptable to issue this irreparable
sanction to a select few while allowing others, equally accountable, to avoid
it? It is acceptable to our criminal justice system for it seems to be standard
operating procedure. Many embrace the death penalty based on the “eye for
an eye” concept. There is certainly some merit to this argument and it seems
quite fair and logical. Unfortunately our use of the death penalty is neither
fair nor logical. Our criminal justice system’s “lip service” to the age-old
concept is an insulting disguise for such an obscurity of fairness and logic.
The death penalty is frivolous and discriminatory in its procedure because
of the unreasonable prices we pay to execute certain groups at much higher
rates than others.
We pay different prices for using a death penalty. Sadly, today more than
ever, the dollar seems to be the endlessly interchangeable standard of value.
We strive to make money, save money and when we spend money we do so with
a valued return in mind. Accordingly, a popular argument contends that we
spend too much money incarcerating prisoners for life. We probably do but
the price tag on issuing a death sentence according to a Florida study is
$3.1 million compared to $1 million for a life sentence; a 3100% difference
(Walker 1994, 108). Imagine your death being valued at $3.1 million – how
flattering. Based on these figures, the difference in the price of an execution
and the price of life behind bars is enough to feed 7,200 starving children
for ten years.
The price of an execution is amazing. Naturally, for such a price, we should
consider our “valued” return. In return for an execution we receive utter
incapacitation; an essential return indeed but we get the same from a life
sentence at a fraction of the cost. What else do we get? Perhaps we satisfy
a need for revenge. Perhaps we feel that we need to keep revenge alive at
any price. After all, we pay top dollar for it. So who exactly is the target
of our vengeance and why? From 1930 to 1980 executions for whites numbered
1754 compared to 2066 for blacks (Bedau 1982). In 1978 blacks claimed 4888
murder victims. Of these, 536 were white or 12% (Bedau 1982). About half
the death row population was black and 85% of their victims were white (Bedau
1982). Blacks who kill whites have a 25% chance of receiving the death penalty
while whites have a 0% chance of receiving it for killing a black. For a
black person, killing a white person could be deadly.
Our criminal justice system’s use of the death penalty appears increasingly
void of rationale when we consider the other prices we pay. Executions take
up to fifteen years or longer (Walker 1994,106). We not only pay for executions
but incarceration as well! There is also the ultimate price. In the wake
of the criminal justice system’s quest to lethally condemn a specific offender,
some innocently accused are gassed, hanged and electrocuted in the name of
retribution. There are twenty-three known cases of the innocent being put
to death by the “state” (Walker 1994,106). Oops. The process of the death
penalty is not only frivolous. It is reckless as well.
The criminal justice system is discriminatory in its use of the death penalty.
If the overwhelming bias in the process of the death penalty isn’t convincing
then perhaps the phenomenal expenditures are. Either way we look we find
a gross absurdity. The funding of the death penalty is frivolous, its fairness
is unrealistic and its process as a whole is unconscionable.
Let us suppose that killing as a form of punishment is a moral and universally
accepted practice. Would it then be acceptable to issue this irreparable
sanction to a select few while allowing others, equally accountable, to avoid
it? It is acceptable to our criminal justice system for it seems to be standard
operating procedure. Many embrace the death penalty based on the “eye for
an eye” concept. There is certainly some merit to this argument and it seems
quite fair and logical. Unfortunately our use of the death penalty is neither
fair nor logical. Our criminal justice system’s “lip service” to the age-old
concept is an insulting disguise for such an obscurity of fairness and logic.
The death penalty is frivolous and discriminatory in its procedure because
of the unreasonable prices we pay to execute certain groups at much higher
rates than others.
We pay different prices for using a death penalty. Sadly, today more than
ever, the dollar seems to be the endlessly interchangeable standard of value.
We strive to make money, save money and when we spend money we do so with
a valued return in mind. Accordingly, a popular argument contends that we
spend too much money incarcerating prisoners for life. We probably do but
the price tag on issuing a death sentence according to a Florida study is
$3.1 million compared to $1 million for a life sentence; a 3100% difference
(Walker 1994, 108). Imagine your death being valued at $3.1 million – how
flattering. Based on these figures, the difference in the price of an execution
and the price of life behind bars is enough to feed 7,200 starving children
for ten years.
The price of an execution is amazing. Naturally, for such a price, we should
consider our “valued” return. In return for an execution we receive utter
incapacitation; an essential return indeed but we get the same from a life
sentence at a fraction of the cost. What else do we get? Perhaps we satisfy
a need for revenge. Perhaps we feel that we need to keep revenge alive at
any price. After all, we pay top dollar for it. So who exactly is the target
of our vengeance and why? From 1930 to 1980 executions for whites numbered
1754 compared to 2066 for blacks (Bedau 1982). In 1978 blacks claimed 4888
murder victims. Of these, 536 were white or 12% (Bedau 1982). About half
the death row population was black and 85% of their victims were white (Bedau
1982). Blacks who kill whites have a 25% chance of receiving the death penalty
while whites have a 0% chance of receiving it for killing a black. For a
black person, killing a white person could be deadly.
Our criminal justice system’s use of the death penalty appears increasingly
void of rationale when we consider the other prices we pay. Executions take
up to fifteen years or longer (Walker 1994,106). We not only pay for executions
but incarceration as well! There is also the ultimate price. In the wake
of the criminal justice system’s quest to lethally condemn a specific offender,
some innocently accused are gassed, hanged and electrocuted in the name of
retribution. There are twenty-three known cases of the innocent being put
to death by the “state” (Walker 1994,106). Oops. The process of the death
penalty is not only frivolous. It is reckless as well.
The criminal justice system is discriminatory in its use of the death penalty.
If the overwhelming bias in the process of the death penalty isn’t convincing
then perhaps the phenomenal expenditures are. Either way we look we find
a gross absurdity. The funding of the death penalty is frivolous, its fairness
is unrealistic and its process as a whole is unconscionable.
Let us suppose that killing as a form of punishment is a moral and universally
accepted practice. Would it then be acceptable to issue this irreparable
sanction to a select few while allowing others, equally accountable, to avoid
it? It is acceptable to our criminal justice system for it seems to be standard
operating procedure. Many embrace the death penalty based on the “eye for
an eye” concept. There is certainly some merit to this argument and it seems
quite fair and logical. Unfortunately our use of the death penalty is neither
fair nor logical. Our criminal justice system’s “lip service” to the age-old
concept is an insulting disguise for such an obscurity of fairness and logic.
The death penalty is frivolous and discriminatory in its procedure because
of the unreasonable prices we pay to execute certain groups at much higher
rates than others.
We pay different prices for using a death penalty. Sadly, today more than
ever, the dollar seems to be the endlessly interchangeable standard of value.
We strive to make money, save money and when we spend money we do so with
a valued return in mind. Accordingly, a popular argument contends that we
spend too much money incarcerating prisoners for life. We probably do but
the price tag on issuing a death sentence according to a Florida study is
$3.1 million compared to $1 million for a life sentence; a 3100% difference
(Walker 1994, 108). Imagine your death being valued at $3.1 million – how
flattering. Based on these figures, the difference in the price of an execution
and the price of life behind bars is enough to feed 7,200 starving children
for ten years.
The price of an execution is amazing. Naturally, for such a price, we should
consider our “valued” return. In return for an execution we receive utter
incapacitation; an essential return indeed but we get the same from a life
sentence at a fraction of the cost. What else do we get? Perhaps we satisfy
a need for revenge. Perhaps we feel that we need to keep revenge alive at
any price. After all, we pay top dollar for it. So who exactly is the target
of our vengeance and why? From 1930 to 1980 executions for whites numbered
1754 compared to 2066 for blacks (Bedau 1982). In 1978 blacks claimed 4888
murder victims. Of these, 536 were white or 12% (Bedau 1982). About half
the death row population was black and 85% of their victims were white (Bedau
1982). Blacks who kill whites have a 25% chance of receiving the death penalty
while whites have a 0% chance of receiving it for killing a black. For a
black person, killing a white person could be deadly.
Our criminal justice system’s use of the death penalty appears increasingly
void of rationale when we consider the other prices we pay. Executions take
up to fifteen years or longer (Walker 1994,106). We not only pay for executions
but incarceration as well! There is also the ultimate price. In the wake
of the criminal justice system’s quest to lethally condemn a specific offender,
some innocently accused are gassed, hanged and electrocuted in the name of
retribution. There are twenty-three known cases of the innocent being put
to death by the “state” (Walker 1994,106). Oops. The process of the death
penalty is not only frivolous. It is reckless as well.
The criminal justice system is discriminatory in its use of the death penalty.
If the overwhelming bias in the process of the death penalty isn’t convincing
then perhaps the phenomenal expenditures are. Either way we look we find
a gross absurdity. The funding of the death penalty is frivolous, its fairness
is unrealistic and its process as a whole is unconscionable.