Реферат на тему Descarte 2 Essay Research Paper DescartesHow does
Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-02Поможем написать учебную работу
Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.
Descarte 2 Essay, Research Paper
Descartes
How does Descartes try to extricate himself from the sceptical
doubts that he has raised? Does he succeed?
by Tom Nuttall
[All page references and quotations from the Meditations are
taken from the 1995 Everyman edition]
In the Meditations, Descartes embarks upon what Bernard Williams
has called the project of ‘Pure Enquiry’ to discover certain,
indubitable foundations for knowledge. By subjecting everything
to doubt Descartes hoped to discover whatever was immune to it.
In order to best understand how and why Descartes builds his
epistemological system up from his foundations in the way that he
does, it is helpful to gain an understanding of the intellectual
background of the 17th century that provided the motivation for
his work.
We can discern three distinct influences on Descartes, three
conflicting world-views that fought for prominence in his day.
The first was what remained of the mediaeval scholastic
philosophy, largely based on Aristotelian science and Christian
theology. Descartes had been taught according to this outlook
during his time at the Jesuit college La Flech_ and it had an
important influence on his work, as we shall see later. The
second was the scepticism that had made a sudden impact on the
intellectual world, mainly as a reaction to the scholastic
outlook. This scepticism was strongly influenced by the work of
the Pyrrhonians as handed down from antiquity by Sextus
Empiricus, which claimed that, as there is never a reason to
believe p that is better than a reason not to believe p, we
should forget about trying to discover the nature of reality and
live by appearance alone. This attitude was best exemplified in
the work of Michel de Montaigne, who mockingly dismissed the
attempts of theologians and scientists to understand the nature
of God and the universe respectively. Descartes felt the force of
sceptical arguments and, while not being sceptically disposed
himself, came to believe that scepticism towards knowledge was
the best way to discover what is certain: by applying sceptical
doubt to all our beliefs, we can discover which of them are
indubitable, and thus form an adequate foundation for knowledge.
The third world-view resulted largely from the work of the new
scientists; Galileo, Copernicus, Bacon et al. Science had finally
begun to assert itself and shake off its dated Aristotelian
prejudices. Coherent theories about the world and its place in
the universe were being constructed and many of those who were
aware of this work became very optimistic about the influence it
could have. Descartes was a child of the scientific revolution,
but felt that until sceptical concerns were dealt with, science
would always have to contend with Montaigne and his cronies,
standing on the sidelines and laughing at science’s pretenses to
knowledge. Descartes’ project, then, was to use the tools of the
sceptic to disprove the sceptical thesis by discovering certain
knowledge that could subsequently be used as the foundation of a
new science, in which knowledge about the external world was as
certain as knowledge about mathematics. It was also to hammer the
last nail into the coffin of scholasticism, but also, arguably,
to show that God still had a vital r_le to play in the discovery
of knowledge.
Meditation One describes Descartes’ method of doubt. By its
conclusion, Descartes has seemingly subjected all of his beliefs
to the strongest and most hyberbolic of doubts. He invokes the
nightmarish notion of an all-powerful, malign demon who could be
deceiving him in the realm of sensory experience, in his very
understanding of matter and even in the simplest cases of
mathematical or logical truths. The doubts may be obscure, but
this is the strength of the method – the weakness of criteria for
what makes a doubt reasonable means that almost anything can
count as a doubt, and therefore whatever withstands doubt must be
something epistemologically formidable.
In Meditation Two, Descartes hits upon the indubitable principle
he has been seeking. He exists, at least when he thinks he
exists. The cogito (Descartes’ proof of his own existence) has
been the source of a great deal of discussion ever since
Descartes first formulated it in the 1637 Discourse on Method,
and, I believe, a great deal of misinterpretation (quite possibly
as a result of Descartes’ repeated contradictions of his own
position in subsequent writings). Many commentators have fallen
prey to the tempting interpretation of the cogito as either
syllogism or enthymeme. This view holds that Descartes asserts
that he is thinking, that he believes it axiomatic that ‘whatever
thinks must exist’ and therefore that he logically concludes that
he exists. This view, it seems to me, is wrong. It should be
stated on no occasion, in the Meditations, does Descartes write
‘I am thinking, therefore I am’, nor anything directly
equivalent. Rather, he says:
“Doubtless, then, that I exist and, let him deceive me as
he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as
I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in
fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and carefully
considered, that this proposition I am, I exist, is necessarily
true each time it is expressed by me or conceived in my mind.”
(p. 80).
The point here is that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the
proposition ‘I exist’ when one utters it. It is an indubitable
proposition, and one that will necessarily be presupposed in
every attack of the sceptic. Descartes is not yet entitled to use
syllogisms as the possibility of the malign demon is still very
much alive. As an aside, Descartes himself denies that the cogito
is a syllogism, although it should be mentioned that in some of
the Replies to Objections he seems to assert that it is in fact
a syllogism. Finally, in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii,
Descartes denies the usefulness of syllogisms as a means to
knowledge.
I believe that, given Descartes’ project, it is fair to grant him
that the cogito deserves the status he bestows upon it. For can
there be anything more certain than something that is so forceful
and so powerful that every time it is presented to our mind we
are forced to assent to it?
What Descartes did here was to jiggle about the way philosophy
normally approaches the construction of knowledge structures. By
starting with self-knowledge, he elevates the subjective above
the objective and forces his epistemology to rest upon the
knowledge he has of his own self (and inadvertently sets the tone
for the next 300 years of philosophy). This leaves him with a
problem. He can know his own existence, that he is a thinking
thing and the contents of his consciousness, but how can any of
this ever lead to any knowledge of anything outside of himself?
The answer is that, by itself, it can’t. Descartes, in the third
Meditation, attempts to prove the existence of God, defined as a
being with all perfections. This proof is to be derived from his
idea of a God, defined as a being with all perfections. So far,
so good – Descartes examines the contents of his consciousness
and discovers within it this idea, and we can allow him this. At
this point, however, he introduces a whole series of scholastic
principles concerning different modes of causation and reality
without proper justification:
“For, without doubt, those [ideas considered as images, as
opposed to modes of consciousness] that represent substances are
something more, and contain in themselves, so to speak, more
objective reality, that is, participate by representation in
higher degrees of being or perfection than those that represent
only modes or accidents; and again the idea by which I conceive a
God has certainly in it more objective reality than those ideas
by which finite substances are represented.
Now it is manifest by the natural light that there must be
at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in
its effect; for whence can the effect draw its reality if not
from its cause? And how could the cause communicate to it this
reality unless it possessed it in itself?”
Whence do these principles draw their indubitability? Even if we
grant that it is contrary to natural reason that an effect can
have greater ‘reality’ than its cause, that the concepts of modes
and substances are coherent with Descartes’ method, let alone
possess the properties that he ascribes to them, then surely we
can still bring the malign demon into play? Is it not possible
that this all- powerful demon could bring it about that Descartes
has a notion of a being with all possible perfections that he
calls God? No, says Descartes, because the notion (representing
something perfect) would then have more objective reality than
the demon (as something evil and thus imperfect) has formal
reality, and ‘it is manifest by the natural light’ that this is
not possible. But why not? Maybe the demon has just made it seem
impossible, and it seems that Descartes has no answer to this.
Further problems remain. Cosmological arguments for God invoking
the notion of causation have always had to contend with the
problem of the cause of God. For if all events (or ideas) are
caused ultimately by God, then what about God Himself? Why should
He be exempt from this rule? The standard response to this is to
claim that God, being omnipotent, causes Himself. One of the
chief perfections that Descartes attributes to God is that of
’self-existence’, that is, that His existence depends on nothing
else but itself. But if we examine this idea, it seems a little
confused. If God is the efficient cause of God then we are forced
to ask how something that does not yet exist can cause anything.
If God is the formal cause of God, i.e. it is part of the
intrinsic nature of God that he exists – which seems more likely
- then it seems that we have merely a reformulation of the
ontological argument for God’s existence from Meditation 5.
It seems that Descartes may have anticipated the wealth of
criticism that the causal proof of God would inspire, and so,
after explaining how human error and a benevolent, non-deceiving
God are compatible in Meditation Four, he produced in Meditation
Five a version of the mediaeval ontological argument for God’s
existence. Unlike the causal argument, the ontological argument
doesn’t involve the covert import of any new principles. It
simply purports to show that, from an analysis of his own idea of
God, Descartes can show that He necessarily exists. The reasoning
goes like this:
I have ideas of things which have true and immutable natures. If
I perceive clearly and distinctly that a property belongs to an
idea’s true and immutable nature, then it does actually belong to
that nature. I perceive clearly and distinctly that God’s true
and mmutable nature is that of a being with all perfections.
Further, I perceive clearly and distinctly that existence is a
perfection and non-existence a non- perfection. Thus existence
belongs to God’s true and immutable nature. God exists.
One of the interesting things about this argument is that, at
first sight, it does not seem to depend in any way upon anything
that has been proved hitherto. It is an application of pure
logic, an analysis of what we mean when we say ‘God’ and a
inference from that analysis. Descartes explicitly says that an
idea’s true and immutable nature does not in any way depend upon
his thinking it, and thus upon his existence. Once he has
perceived clearly and distinctly that an idea’s true and
immutable nature consists in such-and-such, that is the case
whether or not he thinks it is, or even if he exists or not.
Descartes in fact recognises the primacy of the ontological
argument: “although all the conclusions of the preceding
Meditations were false, the existence of God would pass
with me for a truth at least as certain as I ever judged any
truth of mathematics to be.” If this is true, which it seems to
be, then this argument is only as trustworthy as the faculties
which enabled us to construct it, which are the same faculties
that enable us to know mathematical truths, and so it seems
worthwhile to ask how, under Descartes’ theory, we come to know
mathematical truths. Descartes claims we perceive them clearly
and distinctly. How do we know that what we perceive clearly and
distinctly is true? Because God, being perfect, is no deceiver,
and would not let it be the case that we could ever perceive
something clearly and distinctly without it being the case. It
seems then, that this proof of God, relying on the veracity of
clear and distinct ideas, relies on the certain knowledge that a
non-deceiving God exists. We have another proof of God, the
causal proof as described in Meditation three. But apart from the
patent futility of using one proof of p to construct another
proof of p, on examining the causal proof of God further, we find
that it, too, relies upon a methodology that can only be relied
upon if the divine guarantee is present, for if this guarantee is
not present, then, as I mentioned above, how can we be sure that
the all-powerful demon is not exercising his malignant influence?
This, of course, is the infamous Cartesian circle, first
identified by Arnauld in the Fourth Objections and discussed ever
since. Many philosophers have tried to get Descartes off the hook
in various ways, some by denying that there is a circle and some
by admitting the circularity but denying its significance. I will
here briefly evaluate a few of their arguments.
Some commentators have taken a passage from Descartes’ reply to
the Second set of Objections (Mersenne’s) to indicate that
Descartes is only actually interested in the psychological
significance of fundamental truths. The passage is as follows:
“If a conviction is so firm that that it is impossible for us
ever to have any reason for doubting what we are convinced of,
then there are no further questions for us to ask; we have
everything we could reasonably want.”
Under my interpretation, this is what it is about the cogito
that makes it so important for Descartes, so we cannot have any
argument with the principle expressed by him in the above
passage. But can it help break the circle? When we clearly and
distinctly perceive something, Descartes says, fairly I think,
that this perception compels our assent, that we cannot but
believe it. God’s r_le in the system, to these commentators, is
as a guarantor of our memory regarding clarity and distinctness.
In other words, once we have proved God’s existence, we can
happily know that any memory we have of a clear and distinct idea
regarding x is true i.e. that we really did have a clear and
distinct idea of x. But this does not seem satisfactory, as we
still do not have a divine guarantee for the reasoning that leads
us from the clear and distinct notions we originally have about
God to the proof of His existence. We can give assent to the
clear and distinct notions we have originally; in fact, we are
compelled to give this assent when the notions are presented to
our mind, but the logical steps we take from these ideas to the
final proof is still subject to the evil demon because God is not
yet proven. Furthermore, because these steps are needed, the
memory of the original clear and distinct ideas are themselves
subject to doubt because God is not yet proven. It seems that the
only way either of the proofs of God could be accepted would be
if we had an original clear and distinct perception of God
directly presented to our mind (qualitatively similar to the
cogito). But this in itself would make any future proofs
redundant. Interestingly, this sounds quite similar to a divine
revelation.
Harry Frankfurt, in his book ‘Demons, Dreamers and Madmen’, has
argued that what Descartes is actually looking for is a coherent,
indubitable set of beliefs about the universe. Whether they are
‘true’ or not is irrelevant. Perfect certainty is totally
compatible with absolute falsity. Our certainty may not coincide
precisely with ‘God’s’ truth, but should this matter?:
“Reason can give us certainty. It can serve to establish beliefs
in which there is no risk of betrayal. This certainty is all we
need and all we demand. Perhaps our certainties do not coincide
with God’s truth But this divine or absolute truth, since it is
outside the range of our faculties and cannot undermine our
certainties, need be of no concern to us.” (Frankfurt, p 184)
This is almost a Kantian approach to knowledge, where we as
humans only concern ourselves with the phenomena of objects as
they present themselves to us, not with the objects in
themselves. Can we ascribe this view to Descartes? It’s tempting,
given what we have said above regarding the prime importance of
indubitability, but it would seem that a God presenting ideas to
us in a form which doesn’t correspond to reality, and then giving
us a strong disposition to believe that they do correspond to
reality would be a deceiving God and contrary to Descartes’
notion of Him. Thus the belief set would not be coherent.
Perhaps, as we do not have clear and distinct ideas of the bodies
we perceive, and as the divine guarantee only extends as far as
clear and distinct ideas, we are being too hasty in judging that
reality is how it appears to be and if we stopped to meditate
further we would see that reality is actually like something
else. But aside from the fact that this seems unlikely,
Descartes never seemed to envisage the possibility.
So much for the Cartesian circle. Where does this leave the
ontological argument, which we had only just begun to discuss?
Aside from the methodological difficulties, there do seem to two
further problems with it. The first has been noted by almost
every student of Descartes over the years – that of the
description of existence as a property. Put briefly, this
objection states that existence is not a property like ‘red’ or
‘hairy’ or ‘three-sided’ that can be applied to a subject, and
thus it makes no sense to say that existence is part of
something’s essence. If we assert that x is y, we are already
asserting the existence of x as soon as we mention it, prior to
any application of a predicate. from the beginning. In
other words, to say ‘x exists’ is to utter a tautology and to say
that ‘x doesn’t exist’ is to contradict oneself. So how can
sentences of the form ‘x doesn’t exist’ make sense? one may well
ask. It is because these sentences are shorthand for ‘the idea I
have of x has no corresponding reality’ and it was to solve
problems like this that Bertrand Russell constructed his theory
of descriptions. To add existence to an idea doesn’t just make it
an idea with a new property, it changes it from an idea into an
existent entity.
Finally, if Descartes is right, there seems no reason why we
cannot construct any other idea whose essence includes
existence. For instance, if I conjure up the idea of an existent
purple building that resembles the Taj Mahal’, then it is the
true and immutable nature of this idea that it is a building,
that this building resembles the Taj Mahal, that the building is
purple, and that it exists. But no such building does exist, as
far as I am aware, and if it did exist, its existence would not
be necessary, but contingent. This in itself is enough, I think,
to show that the ontological argument is false.
Once we have destroyed Descartes’ proofs of the existence of God,
the edifice of knowledge necessarily comes tumbling down with
them, as we find that almost everything Descartes believes in is
dependent on God’s nature as a non-deceiver:
“I remark that the certitude of all other truths is so absolutely
dependent on it, that without this knowledge it is impossible
ever to know anything perfectly.” (p.115)
The only possible exceptions are those assent-compelling beliefs
such as the cogito. Even these, however, are doubtful when we
are not thinking about them, and the above passage does give
weight to Edwin Curley’s argument that:
“Descartes would hold that the proposition “I exist” is fully
certain only if the rest of the argument of the Meditations goes
through. We must buy all or nothing.”
This is not the end of the story, though. As far as Descartes is
concerned, by the end of Meditation Five, he has produced two
powerful proofs of God, has a clear and distinct notion of his
own self, has a criterion for truth, knows how to avoid error and
is beginning to form ideas regarding our knowledge of corporeal
bodies.. And so it remains only to explain why we are fully
justified in believing in corporeal bodies, and also to draw the
ideas of Meditation Two regarding self-knowledge to their full
conclusion.
Regarding the nature of corporeal bodies and our knowledge of
them, it seems to me that, given his premises, the conclusions
Descartes draws in Meditation Six are generally the correct ones.
He again invokes the causal to argue that the ideas of bodies we
have within our minds must be caused by something with at least
as much formal reality as the ideas have objective reality. We
could theoretically be producing these ideas, but Descartes
dismisses this possibility for two reasons – firstly, that the
idea of corporeality does not presuppose thought and secondly
that our will seems to have no effect on what we perceive or
don’t perceive. (This second argument seems to me to ignore
dreaming, in which what we perceive derives from us but is
independent of our will). The ideas, then, could come from God,
or from another being superior to us but inferior to God. But
this, too, is impossible, argues Descartes, as if it were the
case that God produces the ideas of bodies in us, then the very
strong inclination we have towards believing that the idea-
producing bodies resemble the ideas we have would be false and
thus God would be allowing us to be deceived which is not
permissible. The same would apply if any other being were
producing these ideas. Thus, concludes Descartes, it is most
likely that our ideas of corporeal bodies are actually caused by
bodies resembling those ideas. We cannot be certain, however, as
we cannot claim to have clear and distinct notions of everything
we perceive. We can, however, claim certainty with regard to
those properties of bodies which we do know with clarity and
distinction; namely, size, figure (shape), position, motion,
substance, duration and number (not all of these assertions are
justified). Obviously we cannot claim that we know these
properties for specific bodies with clarity and distinction, for
to do so would leave open the uestion of why it is that
astronomy and the senses attribute different sizes to stars. What
Descartes means is that we can be sure that these primary
qualities exist in bodies in the same way that they do in our
ideas of bodies. This cannot be claimed for qualities such as
heat, colour, taste and smell, of which our ideas are so confused
and vague that we must always reserve judgement. (This conclusion
is actually quite similar to the one John Locke drew fifty years
later in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding.)
I think we can grant this reasoning, with the caveat regarding
dreaming that I noted above, and of course the other unproved
reasonings that Descartes exhumes here, such as the causal
principle. Furthermore, it seems to be further proof that
Descartes does believe we can get to know objects in themselves
to a certain extent.
Finally, I turn to Descartes’ argument for the distinction of
mind and body. Descartes believes he has shown the mind to be
better known than the body in Meditation Two. In Meditation Six
he goes on to claim that, as he knows his mind and knows clearly
and distinctly that its essence consists purely of thought, and
that bodies’ essences consist purely of extension, that he can
conceive of his mind and body as existing separately. By the
power of God, anything that can be clearly and distinctly
conceived of as existing separately from something else can be
created as existing separately. At this point, Descartes makes
the apparent logical leap to claiming that the mind and body have
been created separately, without justification. Most commentators
agree that this is not justified, and further, that just because
I can conceive of my mind existing independently of my body it
does not necessarily follow that it does so. In defence of
Descartes, Saul Kripke has suggested that Descartes may have
anticipated a modern strand of modal logic that holds that if
x=y, then L (x=y). In other words, if x is identical to y then it
is necessarily identical to it. From this it follows that if it
is logically possible that x and y have different properties then
they are distinct. In this instance, that means that because I
can clearly and distinctly conceive of my mind and body as
existing separately, then they are distinct. The argument, like
much modern work on identity, is too technical and involved to
explore here in much depth. But suffice to say that we can
clearly and distinctly conceive of Dr Jekyll and Mr. Hyde as
being distinct and yet they are identical, necessarily so under
Kripke’s theory. It is doubtful that Kripke can come to
Descartes’ aid here and Descartes needs further argument to prove
that the mind and the body are distinct.
And so we finish our discussion of Descartes’ attempts to
extricate himself from the sceptical doubts he has set up for
himself. As mentioned previously, the ultimate conclusion to draw
regarding the success of the enterprise that Descartes set for
himself must be that he failed. When the whole epistemological
structure is so heavily dependent on one piece of knowledge – in
this case the knowledge that God exists – then a denial of that
knowledge destroys the whole structure. All that we can really
grant Descartes – and this is certainly contentious – is that he
can rightly claim that when a clear and distinct idea presents
itself to his mind, he cannot but give his assent to this idea,
and furthermore, that while this assent is being granted, the
clear and distinct idea can be justly used as a foundation for
knowledge. The most this gets us – and this is not a little – is
the knowledge of our own existence each time we assert it. But
Descartes’ project should not be judged by us as a failure – the
fact that he addressed topics of great and lasting interest, and
provided us with a method we can both understand and utilise
fruitfully, speaks for itself.
Bibliography
1. Descartes, Ren_ A Discourse on Method, Meditations and
Principles of Philosophy trans. John Veitch. The Everyman’s
Library, 1995.
Descartes, Ren_ The Philosophical Writings of Descartes volume I
and II ed. and trans. John Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D.
Murdoch. Cambridge, 1985.
Frankfurt, Harry Demons, Dreamers and Madmen. Bobbs-Merrill,
1970.
Curley, Edwin Descartes Against the Skeptics. Oxford, 1978.
Vesey, Godfrey Descartes: Father of Modern Philosophy. Open
University Press, 1971.
Sorrell, Tom Descartes: Reason and Experience. Open University
Press, 1982.
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy ed. Ted Honderich. Oxford
University Press, 1985.
Cottingham, John Descartes. Oxford, 1986. Williams, Bernard
Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth, 1978.
Russell, Bertrand The History of Western Philosophy. George Allen
and Unwin, 1961. 11. Kripke, Saul Naming and Necessity. Oxford
1980.>
Descartes
How does Descartes try to extricate himself from the sceptical
doubts that he has raised? Does he succeed?
by Tom Nuttall
[All page references and quotations from the Meditations are
taken from the 1995 Everyman edition]
In the Meditations, Descartes embarks upon what Bernard Williams
has called the project of ‘Pure Enquiry’ to discover certain,
indubitable foundations for knowledge. By subjecting everything
to doubt Descartes hoped to discover whatever was immune to it.
In order to best understand how and why Descartes builds his
epistemological system up from his foundations in the way that he
does, it is helpful to gain an understanding of the intellectual
background of the 17th century that provided the motivation for
his work.
We can discern three distinct influences on Descartes, three
conflicting world-views that fought for prominence in his day.
The first was what remained of the mediaeval scholastic
philosophy, largely based on Aristotelian science and Christian
theology. Descartes had been taught according to this outlook
during his time at the Jesuit college La Flech_ and it had an
important influence on his work, as we shall see later. The
second was the scepticism that had made a sudden impact on the
intellectual world, mainly as a reaction to the scholastic
outlook. This scepticism was strongly influenced by the work of
the Pyrrhonians as handed down from antiquity by Sextus
Empiricus, which claimed that, as there is never a reason to
believe p that is better than a reason not to believe p, we
should forget about trying to discover the nature of reality and
live by appearance alone. This attitude was best exemplified in
the work of Michel de Montaigne, who mockingly dismissed the
attempts of theologians and scientists to understand the nature
of God and the universe respectively. Descartes felt the force of
sceptical arguments and, while not being sceptically disposed
himself, came to believe that scepticism towards knowledge was
the best way to discover what is certain: by applying sceptical
doubt to all our beliefs, we can discover which of them are
indubitable, and thus form an adequate foundation for knowledge.
The third world-view resulted largely from the work of the new
scientists; Galileo, Copernicus, Bacon et al. Science had finally
begun to assert itself and shake off its dated Aristotelian
prejudices. Coherent theories about the world and its place in
the universe were being constructed and many of those who were
aware of this work became very optimistic about the influence it
could have. Descartes was a child of the scientific revolution,
but felt that until sceptical concerns were dealt with, science
would always have to contend with Montaigne and his cronies,
standing on the sidelines and laughing at science’s pretenses to
knowledge. Descartes’ project, then, was to use the tools of the
sceptic to disprove the sceptical thesis by discovering certain
knowledge that could subsequently be used as the foundation of a
new science, in which knowledge about the external world was as
certain as knowledge about mathematics. It was also to hammer the
last nail into the coffin of scholasticism, but also, arguably,
to show that God still had a vital r_le to play in the discovery
of knowledge.
Meditation One describes Descartes’ method of doubt. By its
conclusion, Descartes has seemingly subjected all of his beliefs
to the strongest and most hyberbolic of doubts. He invokes the
nightmarish notion of an all-powerful, malign demon who could be
deceiving him in the realm of sensory experience, in his very
understanding of matter and even in the simplest cases of
mathematical or logical truths. The doubts may be obscure, but
this is the strength of the method – the weakness of criteria for
what makes a doubt reasonable means that almost anything can
count as a doubt, and therefore whatever withstands doubt must be
something epistemologically formidable.
In Meditation Two, Descartes hits upon the indubitable principle
he has been seeking. He exists, at least when he thinks he
exists. The cogito (Descartes’ proof of his own existence) has
been the source of a great deal of discussion ever since
Descartes first formulated it in the 1637 Discourse on Method,
and, I believe, a great deal of misinterpretation (quite possibly
as a result of Descartes’ repeated contradictions of his own
position in subsequent writings). Many commentators have fallen
prey to the tempting interpretation of the cogito as either
syllogism or enthymeme. This view holds that Descartes asserts
that he is thinking, that he believes it axiomatic that ‘whatever
thinks must exist’ and therefore that he logically concludes that
he exists. This view, it seems to me, is wrong. It should be
stated on no occasion, in the Meditations, does Descartes write
‘I am thinking, therefore I am’, nor anything directly
equivalent. Rather, he says:
“Doubtless, then, that I exist and, let him deceive me as
he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as
I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in
fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and carefully
considered, that this proposition I am, I exist, is necessarily
true each time it is expressed by me or conceived in my mind.”
(p. 80).
The point here is that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the
proposition ‘I exist’ when one utters it. It is an indubitable
proposition, and one that will necessarily be presupposed in
every attack of the sceptic. Descartes is not yet entitled to use
syllogisms as the possibility of the malign demon is still very
much alive. As an aside, Descartes himself denies that the cogito
is a syllogism, although it should be mentioned that in some of
the Replies to Objections he seems to assert that it is in fact
a syllogism. Finally, in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii,
Descartes denies the usefulness of syllogisms as a means to
knowledge.
I believe that, given Descartes’ project, it is fair to grant him
that the cogito deserves the status he bestows upon it. For can
there be anything more certain than something that is so forceful
and so powerful that every time it is presented to our mind we
are forced to assent to it?
What Descartes did here was to jiggle about the way philosophy
normally approaches the construction of knowledge structures. By
starting with self-knowledge, he elevates the subjective above
the objective and forces his epistemology to rest upon the
knowledge he has of his own self (and inadvertently sets the tone
for the next 300 years of philosophy). This leaves him with a
problem. He can know his own existence, that he is a thinking
thing and the contents of his consciousness, but how can any of
this ever lead to any knowledge of anything outside of himself?
The answer is that, by itself, it can’t. Descartes, in the third
Meditation, attempts to prove the existence of God, defined as a
being with all perfections. This proof is to be derived from his
idea of a God, defined as a being with all perfections. So far,
so good – Descartes examines the contents of his consciousness
and discovers within it this idea, and we can allow him this. At
this point, however, he introduces a whole series of scholastic
principles concerning different modes of causation and reality
without proper justification:
“For, without doubt, those [ideas considered as images, as
opposed to modes of consciousness] that represent substances are
something more, and contain in themselves, so to speak, more
objective reality, that is, participate by representation in
higher degrees of being or perfection than those that represent
only modes or accidents; and again the idea by which I conceive a
God has certainly in it more objective reality than those ideas
by which finite substances are represented.
Now it is manifest by the natural light that there must be
at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in
its effect; for whence can the effect draw its reality if not
from its cause? And how could the cause communicate to it this
reality unless it possessed it in itself?”
Whence do these principles draw their indubitability? Even if we
grant that it is contrary to natural reason that an effect can
have greater ‘reality’ than its cause, that the concepts of modes
and substances are coherent with Descartes’ method, let alone
possess the properties that he ascribes to them, then surely we
can still bring the malign demon into play? Is it not possible
that this all- powerful demon could bring it about that Descartes
has a notion of a being with all possible perfections that he
calls God? No, says Descartes, because the notion (representing
something perfect) would then have more objective reality than
the demon (as something evil and thus imperfect) has formal
reality, and ‘it is manifest by the natural light’ that this is
not possible. But why not? Maybe the demon has just made it seem
impossible, and it seems that Descartes has no answer to this.
Further problems remain. Cosmological arguments for God invoking
the notion of causation have always had to contend with the
problem of the cause of God. For if all events (or ideas) are
caused ultimately by God, then what about God Himself? Why should
He be exempt from this rule? The standard response to this is to
claim that God, being omnipotent, causes Himself. One of the
chief perfections that Descartes attributes to God is that of
’self-existence’, that is, that His existence depends on nothing
else but itself. But if we examine this idea, it seems a little
confused. If God is the efficient cause of God then we are forced
to ask how something that does not yet exist can cause anything.
If God is the formal cause of God, i.e. it is part of the
intrinsic nature of God that he exists – which seems more likely
- then it seems that we have merely a reformulation of the
ontological argument for God’s existence from Meditation 5.
It seems that Descartes may have anticipated the wealth of
criticism that the causal proof of God would inspire, and so,
after explaining how human error and a benevolent, non-deceiving
God are compatible in Meditation Four, he produced in Meditation
Five a version of the mediaeval ontological argument for God’s
existence. Unlike the causal argument, the ontological argument
doesn’t involve the covert import of any new principles. It
simply purports to show that, from an analysis of his own idea of
God, Descartes can show that He necessarily exists. The reasoning
goes like this:
I have ideas of things which have true and immutable natures. If
I perceive clearly and distinctly that a property belongs to an
idea’s true and immutable nature, then it does actually belong to
that nature. I perceive clearly and distinctly that God’s true
and mmutable nature is that of a being with all perfections.
Further, I perceive clearly and distinctly that existence is a
perfection and non-existence a non- perfection. Thus existence
belongs to God’s true and immutable nature. God exists.
One of the interesting things about this argument is that, at
first sight, it does not seem to depend in any way upon anything
that has been proved hitherto. It is an application of pure
logic, an analysis of what we mean when we say ‘God’ and a
inference from that analysis. Descartes explicitly says that an
idea’s true and immutable nature does not in any way depend upon
his thinking it, and thus upon his existence. Once he has
perceived clearly and distinctly that an idea’s true and
immutable nature consists in such-and-such, that is the case
whether or not he thinks it is, or even if he exists or not.
Descartes in fact recognises the primacy of the ontological
argument: “although all the conclusions of the preceding
Meditations were false, the existence of God would pass
with me for a truth at least as certain as I ever judged any
truth of mathematics to be.” If this is true, which it seems to
be, then this argument is only as trustworthy as the faculties
which enabled us to construct it, which are the same faculties
that enable us to know mathematical truths, and so it seems
worthwhile to ask how, under Descartes’ theory, we come to know
mathematical truths. Descartes claims we perceive them clearly
and distinctly. How do we know that what we perceive clearly and
distinctly is true? Because God, being perfect, is no deceiver,
and would not let it be the case that we could ever perceive
something clearly and distinctly without it being the case. It
seems then, that this proof of God, relying on the veracity of
clear and distinct ideas, relies on the certain knowledge that a
non-deceiving God exists. We have another proof of God, the
causal proof as described in Meditation three. But apart from the
patent futility of using one proof of p to construct another
proof of p, on examining the causal proof of God further, we find
that it, too, relies upon a methodology that can only be relied
upon if the divine guarantee is present, for if this guarantee is
not present, then, as I mentioned above, how can we be sure that
the all-powerful demon is not exercising his malignant influence?
This, of course, is the infamous Cartesian circle, first
identified by Arnauld in the Fourth Objections and discussed ever
since. Many philosophers have tried to get Descartes off the hook
in various ways, some by denying that there is a circle and some
by admitting the circularity but denying its significance. I will
here briefly evaluate a few of their arguments.
Some commentators have taken a passage from Descartes’ reply to
the Second set of Objections (Mersenne’s) to indicate that
Descartes is only actually interested in the psychological
significance of fundamental truths. The passage is as follows:
“If a conviction is so firm that that it is impossible for us
ever to have any reason for doubting what we are convinced of,
then there are no further questions for us to ask; we have
everything we could reasonably want.”
Under my interpretation, this is what it is about the cogito
that makes it so important for Descartes, so we cannot have any
argument with the principle expressed by him in the above
passage. But can it help break the circle? When we clearly and
distinctly perceive something, Descartes says, fairly I think,
that this perception compels our assent, that we cannot but
believe it. God’s r_le in the system, to these commentators, is
as a guarantor of our memory regarding clarity and distinctness.
In other words, once we have proved God’s existence, we can
happily know that any memory we have of a clear and distinct idea
regarding x is true i.e. that we really did have a clear and
distinct idea of x. But this does not seem satisfactory, as we
still do not have a divine guarantee for the reasoning that leads
us from the clear and distinct notions we originally have about
God to the proof of His existence. We can give assent to the
clear and distinct notions we have originally; in fact, we are
compelled to give this assent when the notions are presented to
our mind, but the logical steps we take from these ideas to the
final proof is still subject to the evil demon because God is not
yet proven. Furthermore, because these steps are needed, the
memory of the original clear and distinct ideas are themselves
subject to doubt because God is not yet proven. It seems that the
only way either of the proofs of God could be accepted would be
if we had an original clear and distinct perception of God
directly presented to our mind (qualitatively similar to the
cogito). But this in itself would make any future proofs
redundant. Interestingly, this sounds quite similar to a divine
revelation.
Harry Frankfurt, in his book ‘Demons, Dreamers and Madmen’, has
argued that what Descartes is actually looking for is a coherent,
indubitable set of beliefs about the universe. Whether they are
‘true’ or not is irrelevant. Perfect certainty is totally
compatible with absolute falsity. Our certainty may not coincide
precisely with ‘God’s’ truth, but should this matter?:
“Reason can give us certainty. It can serve to establish beliefs
in which there is no risk of betrayal. This certainty is all we
need and all we demand. Perhaps our certainties do not coincide
with God’s truth But this divine or absolute truth, since it is
outside the range of our faculties and cannot undermine our
certainties, need be of no concern to us.” (Frankfurt, p 184)
This is almost a Kantian approach to knowledge, where we as
humans only concern ourselves with the phenomena of objects as
they present themselves to us, not with the objects in
themselves. Can we ascribe this view to Descartes? It’s tempting,
given what we have said above regarding the prime importance of
indubitability, but it would seem that a God presenting ideas to
us in a form which doesn’t correspond to reality, and then giving
us a strong disposition to believe that they do correspond to
reality would be a deceiving God and contrary to Descartes’
notion of Him. Thus the belief set would not be coherent.
Perhaps, as we do not have clear and distinct ideas of the bodies
we perceive, and as the divine guarantee only extends as far as
clear and distinct ideas, we are being too hasty in judging that
reality is how it appears to be and if we stopped to meditate
further we would see that reality is actually like something
else. But aside from the fact that this seems unlikely,
Descartes never seemed to envisage the possibility.
So much for the Cartesian circle. Where does this leave the
ontological argument, which we had only just begun to discuss?
Aside from the methodological difficulties, there do seem to two
further problems with it. The first has been noted by almost
every student of Descartes over the years – that of the
description of existence as a property. Put briefly, this
objection states that existence is not a property like ‘red’ or
‘hairy’ or ‘three-sided’ that can be applied to a subject, and
thus it makes no sense to say that existence is part of
something’s essence. If we assert that x is y, we are already
asserting the existence of x as soon as we mention it, prior to
any application of a predicate. from the beginning. In
other words, to say ‘x exists’ is to utter a tautology and to say
that ‘x doesn’t exist’ is to contradict oneself. So how can
sentences of the form ‘x doesn’t exist’ make sense? one may well
ask. It is because these sentences are shorthand for ‘the idea I
have of x has no corresponding reality’ and it was to solve
problems like this that Bertrand Russell constructed his theory
of descriptions. To add existence to an idea doesn’t just make it
an idea with a new property, it changes it from an idea into an
existent entity.
Finally, if Descartes is right, there seems no reason why we
cannot construct any other idea whose essence includes
existence. For instance, if I conjure up the idea of an existent
purple building that resembles the Taj Mahal’, then it is the
true and immutable nature of this idea that it is a building,
that this building resembles the Taj Mahal, that the building is
purple, and that it exists. But no such building does exist, as
far as I am aware, and if it did exist, its existence would not
be necessary, but contingent. This in itself is enough, I think,
to show that the ontological argument is false.
Once we have destroyed Descartes’ proofs of the existence of God,
the edifice of knowledge necessarily comes tumbling down with
them, as we find that almost everything Descartes believes in is
dependent on God’s nature as a non-deceiver:
“I remark that the certitude of all other truths is so absolutely
dependent on it, that without this knowledge it is impossible
ever to know anything perfectly.” (p.115)
The only possible exceptions are those assent-compelling beliefs
such as the cogito. Even these, however, are doubtful when we
are not thinking about them, and the above passage does give
weight to Edwin Curley’s argument that:
“Descartes would hold that the proposition “I exist” is fully
certain only if the rest of the argument of the Meditations goes
through. We must buy all or nothing.”
This is not the end of the story, though. As far as Descartes is
concerned, by the end of Meditation Five, he has produced two
powerful proofs of God, has a clear and distinct notion of his
own self, has a criterion for truth, knows how to avoid error and
is beginning to form ideas regarding our knowledge of corporeal
bodies.. And so it remains only to explain why we are fully
justified in believing in corporeal bodies, and also to draw the
ideas of Meditation Two regarding self-knowledge to their full
conclusion.
Regarding the nature of corporeal bodies and our knowledge of
them, it seems to me that, given his premises, the conclusions
Descartes draws in Meditation Six are generally the correct ones.
He again invokes the causal to argue that the ideas of bodies we
have within our minds must be caused by something with at least
as much formal reality as the ideas have objective reality. We
could theoretically be producing these ideas, but Descartes
dismisses this possibility for two reasons – firstly, that the
idea of corporeality does not presuppose thought and secondly
that our will seems to have no effect on what we perceive or
don’t perceive. (This second argument seems to me to ignore
dreaming, in which what we perceive derives from us but is
independent of our will). The ideas, then, could come from God,
or from another being superior to us but inferior to God. But
this, too, is impossible, argues Descartes, as if it were the
case that God produces the ideas of bodies in us, then the very
strong inclination we have towards believing that the idea-
producing bodies resemble the ideas we have would be false and
thus God would be allowing us to be deceived which is not
permissible. The same would apply if any other being were
producing these ideas. Thus, concludes Descartes, it is most
likely that our ideas of corporeal bodies are actually caused by
bodies resembling those ideas. We cannot be certain, however, as
we cannot claim to have clear and distinct notions of everything
we perceive. We can, however, claim certainty with regard to
those properties of bodies which we do know with clarity and
distinction; namely, size, figure (shape), position, motion,
substance, duration and number (not all of these assertions are
justified). Obviously we cannot claim that we know these
properties for specific bodies with clarity and distinction, for
to do so would leave open the uestion of why it is that
astronomy and the senses attribute different sizes to stars. What
Descartes means is that we can be sure that these primary
qualities exist in bodies in the same way that they do in our
ideas of bodies. This cannot be claimed for qualities such as
heat, colour, taste and smell, of which our ideas are so confused
and vague that we must always reserve judgement. (This conclusion
is actually quite similar to the one John Locke drew fifty years
later in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding.)
I think we can grant this reasoning, with the caveat regarding
dreaming that I noted above, and of course the other unproved
reasonings that Descartes exhumes here, such as the causal
principle. Furthermore, it seems to be further proof that
Descartes does believe we can get to know objects in themselves
to a certain extent.
Finally, I turn to Descartes’ argument for the distinction of
mind and body. Descartes believes he has shown the mind to be
better known than the body in Meditation Two. In Meditation Six
he goes on to claim that, as he knows his mind and knows clearly
and distinctly that its essence consists purely of thought, and
that bodies’ essences consist purely of extension, that he can
conceive of his mind and body as existing separately. By the
power of God, anything that can be clearly and distinctly
conceived of as existing separately from something else can be
created as existing separately. At this point, Descartes makes
the apparent logical leap to claiming that the mind and body have
been created separately, without justification. Most commentators
agree that this is not justified, and further, that just because
I can conceive of my mind existing independently of my body it
does not necessarily follow that it does so. In defence of
Descartes, Saul Kripke has suggested that Descartes may have
anticipated a modern strand of modal logic that holds that if
x=y, then L (x=y). In other words, if x is identical to y then it
is necessarily identical to it. From this it follows that if it
is logically possible that x and y have different properties then
they are distinct. In this instance, that means that because I
can clearly and distinctly conceive of my mind and body as
existing separately, then they are distinct. The argument, like
much modern work on identity, is too technical and involved to
explore here in much depth. But suffice to say that we can
clearly and distinctly conceive of Dr Jekyll and Mr. Hyde as
being distinct and yet they are identical, necessarily so under
Kripke’s theory. It is doubtful that Kripke can come to
Descartes’ aid here and Descartes needs further argument to prove
that the mind and the body are distinct.
And so we finish our discussion of Descartes’ attempts to
extricate himself from the sceptical doubts he has set up for
himself. As mentioned previously, the ultimate conclusion to draw
regarding the success of the enterprise that Descartes set for
himself must be that he failed. When the whole epistemological
structure is so heavily dependent on one piece of knowledge – in
this case the knowledge that God exists – then a denial of that
knowledge destroys the whole structure. All that we can really
grant Descartes – and this is certainly contentious – is that he
can rightly claim that when a clear and distinct idea presents
itself to his mind, he cannot but give his assent to this idea,
and furthermore, that while this assent is being granted, the
clear and distinct idea can be justly used as a foundation for
knowledge. The most this gets us – and this is not a little – is
the knowledge of our own existence each time we assert it. But
Descartes’ project should not be judged by us as a failure – the
fact that he addressed topics of great and lasting interest, and
provided us with a method we can both understand and utilise
fruitfully, speaks for itself.
Bibliography
1. Descartes, Ren_ A Discourse on Method, Meditations and
Principles of Philosophy trans. John Veitch. The Everyman’s
Library, 1995.
Descartes, Ren_ The Philosophical Writings of Descartes volume I
and II ed. and trans. John Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D.
Murdoch. Cambridge, 1985.
Frankfurt, Harry Demons, Dreamers and Madmen. Bobbs-Merrill,
1970.
Curley, Edwin Descartes Against the Skeptics. Oxford, 1978.
Vesey, Godfrey Descartes: Father of Modern Philosophy. Open
University Press, 1971.
Sorrell, Tom Descartes: Reason and Experience. Open University
Press, 1982.
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy ed. Ted Honderich. Oxford
University Press, 1985.
Cottingham, John Descartes. Oxford, 1986. Williams, Bernard
Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth, 1978.
Russell, Bertrand The History of Western Philosophy. George Allen
and Unwin, 1961. 11. Kripke, Saul Naming and Necessity. Oxford
1980.>
Descartes
How does Descartes try to extricate himself from the sceptical
doubts that he has raised? Does he succeed?
by Tom Nuttall
[All page references and quotations from the Meditations are
taken from the 1995 Everyman edition]
In the Meditations, Descartes embarks upon what Bernard Williams
has called the project of ‘Pure Enquiry’ to discover certain,
indubitable foundations for knowledge. By subjecting everything
to doubt Descartes hoped to discover whatever was immune to it.
In order to best understand how and why Descartes builds his
epistemological system up from his foundations in the way that he
does, it is helpful to gain an understanding of the intellectual
background of the 17th century that provided the motivation for
his work.
We can discern three distinct influences on Descartes, three
conflicting world-views that fought for prominence in his day.
The first was what remained of the mediaeval scholastic
philosophy, largely based on Aristotelian science and Christian
theology. Descartes had been taught according to this outlook
during his time at the Jesuit college La Flech_ and it had an
important influence on his work, as we shall see later. The
second was the scepticism that had made a sudden impact on the
intellectual world, mainly as a reaction to the scholastic
outlook. This scepticism was strongly influenced by the work of
the Pyrrhonians as handed down from antiquity by Sextus
Empiricus, which claimed that, as there is never a reason to
believe p that is better than a reason not to believe p, we
should forget about trying to discover the nature of reality and
live by appearance alone. This attitude was best exemplified in
the work of Michel de Montaigne, who mockingly dismissed the
attempts of theologians and scientists to understand the nature
of God and the universe respectively. Descartes felt the force of
sceptical arguments and, while not being sceptically disposed
himself, came to believe that scepticism towards knowledge was
the best way to discover what is certain: by applying sceptical
doubt to all our beliefs, we can discover which of them are
indubitable, and thus form an adequate foundation for knowledge.
The third world-view resulted largely from the work of the new
scientists; Galileo, Copernicus, Bacon et al. Science had finally
begun to assert itself and shake off its dated Aristotelian
prejudices. Coherent theories about the world and its place in
the universe were being constructed and many of those who were
aware of this work became very optimistic about the influence it
could have. Descartes was a child of the scientific revolution,
but felt that until sceptical concerns were dealt with, science
would always have to contend with Montaigne and his cronies,
standing on the sidelines and laughing at science’s pretenses to
knowledge. Descartes’ project, then, was to use the tools of the
sceptic to disprove the sceptical thesis by discovering certain
knowledge that could subsequently be used as the foundation of a
new science, in which knowledge about the external world was as
certain as knowledge about mathematics. It was also to hammer the
last nail into the coffin of scholasticism, but also, arguably,
to show that God still had a vital r_le to play in the discovery
of knowledge.
Meditation One describes Descartes’ method of doubt. By its
conclusion, Descartes has seemingly subjected all of his beliefs
to the strongest and most hyberbolic of doubts. He invokes the
nightmarish notion of an all-powerful, malign demon who could be
deceiving him in the realm of sensory experience, in his very
understanding of matter and even in the simplest cases of
mathematical or logical truths. The doubts may be obscure, but
this is the strength of the method – the weakness of criteria for
what makes a doubt reasonable means that almost anything can
count as a doubt, and therefore whatever withstands doubt must be
something epistemologically formidable.
In Meditation Two, Descartes hits upon the indubitable principle
he has been seeking. He exists, at least when he thinks he
exists. The cogito (Descartes’ proof of his own existence) has
been the source of a great deal of discussion ever since
Descartes first formulated it in the 1637 Discourse on Method,
and, I believe, a great deal of misinterpretation (quite possibly
as a result of Descartes’ repeated contradictions of his own
position in subsequent writings). Many commentators have fallen
prey to the tempting interpretation of the cogito as either
syllogism or enthymeme. This view holds that Descartes asserts
that he is thinking, that he believes it axiomatic that ‘whatever
thinks must exist’ and therefore that he logically concludes that
he exists. This view, it seems to me, is wrong. It should be
stated on no occasion, in the Meditations, does Descartes write
‘I am thinking, therefore I am’, nor anything directly
equivalent. Rather, he says:
“Doubtless, then, that I exist and, let him deceive me as
he may, he can never bring it about that I am nothing, so long as
I shall be conscious that I am something. So that it must, in
fine, be maintained, all things being maturely and carefully
considered, that this proposition I am, I exist, is necessarily
true each time it is expressed by me or conceived in my mind.”
(p. 80).
The point here is that it is impossible to doubt the truth of the
proposition ‘I exist’ when one utters it. It is an indubitable
proposition, and one that will necessarily be presupposed in
every attack of the sceptic. Descartes is not yet entitled to use
syllogisms as the possibility of the malign demon is still very
much alive. As an aside, Descartes himself denies that the cogito
is a syllogism, although it should be mentioned that in some of
the Replies to Objections he seems to assert that it is in fact
a syllogism. Finally, in the Regulae ad directionem ingenii,
Descartes denies the usefulness of syllogisms as a means to
knowledge.
I believe that, given Descartes’ project, it is fair to grant him
that the cogito deserves the status he bestows upon it. For can
there be anything more certain than something that is so forceful
and so powerful that every time it is presented to our mind we
are forced to assent to it?
What Descartes did here was to jiggle about the way philosophy
normally approaches the construction of knowledge structures. By
starting with self-knowledge, he elevates the subjective above
the objective and forces his epistemology to rest upon the
knowledge he has of his own self (and inadvertently sets the tone
for the next 300 years of philosophy). This leaves him with a
problem. He can know his own existence, that he is a thinking
thing and the contents of his consciousness, but how can any of
this ever lead to any knowledge of anything outside of himself?
The answer is that, by itself, it can’t. Descartes, in the third
Meditation, attempts to prove the existence of God, defined as a
being with all perfections. This proof is to be derived from his
idea of a God, defined as a being with all perfections. So far,
so good – Descartes examines the contents of his consciousness
and discovers within it this idea, and we can allow him this. At
this point, however, he introduces a whole series of scholastic
principles concerning different modes of causation and reality
without proper justification:
“For, without doubt, those [ideas considered as images, as
opposed to modes of consciousness] that represent substances are
something more, and contain in themselves, so to speak, more
objective reality, that is, participate by representation in
higher degrees of being or perfection than those that represent
only modes or accidents; and again the idea by which I conceive a
God has certainly in it more objective reality than those ideas
by which finite substances are represented.
Now it is manifest by the natural light that there must be
at least as much reality in the efficient and total cause as in
its effect; for whence can the effect draw its reality if not
from its cause? And how could the cause communicate to it this
reality unless it possessed it in itself?”
Whence do these principles draw their indubitability? Even if we
grant that it is contrary to natural rea