Реферат на тему Freedom And Reason In Kant Essay Research
Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-04Поможем написать учебную работу
Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.
Freedom And Reason In Kant Essay, Research Paper
Freedom and Reason in Kant
Alice Furnari
24 /2/97
Morality, Kant says, cannot be regarded as a set of rules which prescribe
the means necessary to the achievement of a given end; its rules must be obeyed
without consideration of the consequences that will follow from doing so or not.
A principle that presupposes a desired object as the determinant of the will
cannot give rise to a moral law; that is, the morality of an act of will cannot
be determined by the matter or content of the will for when the will is
materially determined the question of its morality does not arise.
This consideration leads Kant to one of his most important theses. If the
moral character of willing is not determined by the content of what is willed,
it must be determined by the form:” If a rational being can think of his maxims
as universal laws, he can do so only by considering them as principles which
contain the determining ground of the will because of their form and not because
of their matter”. Therefore, the morality of a maxim is determined by its
functioning as a universal law, applicable as a general rule to every rational
agent. Since a moral will must be so in virtue of its form alone, the will must
be capable of a purely formal determination; that is, it must be possible for a
man to act in a certain way for the sole reason that willing in this way is
prescribed by a universal law, no matter what the empirical results will be.
A will to which moral considerations apply must be, in the strictest sense,
a free will, one that can function independently of the laws of natural
causality. The concept of morality, therefore, has to be explained in terms of a
universal moral law, and the ability to will in obedience to such a law leads us
to postulate the freedom. The freedom which Kant is talking about, is not only a
negative freedom consisting in the absence of constraint by empirical causes, it
is also a positive freedom which consists in the ability to make acts of will in
accordance with the moral law, for no other reason than that they are in
accordance with it. Freedom, in this sense, corresponds to Autonomy of the will
and its absence ( any situation in which the will is determined by external
causes ) is called Heteronomy. In obeying the moral law for the sake of the law
alone, the will is autonomous because it is obeying a law which it imposes on
itself.
In the third section of the “Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals”, Kant
answers the problem of the possibility of the Categorical Imperative. Is the
problem to be understood as if the Categorical Imperative is possible, or how it
is possible? In the “Critics of Pure Reason”, the problem regarding the
synthetic a priori judgments concerns just the modality in which they can be
applied. The fact that they are actually possible is proved by the synthetic a
priori judgment contained in sciences as mathematics and physics which are
trustworthy sciences. Metaphysics, however, is not a reliable science and,
therefore, Kant suggests that we should look not only for the modality in which
they can be applied, but also for their reliability. Similarly, the Metaphysics
of Morals must prove the validity of the moral imperative. As Paton suggested,
Kant tries to show not only how the Categorical Imperative is possible, but also
that it is possible.[" Furthermore, we have not asserted the truth of this
proposition, much less professed to have within our power a proof of it. We
simply showed by developing the universally accepted concept of morality, that
autonomy of the will is unavoidably bound up with it, or rather is its very
foundation" par. 445].
The condition for the possibility of the Categorical Imperative is Freedom.
The third section contains a demonstration of Freedom which Kant tries to derive
by means of excluding at least other two ways. A first would be to assert that
Freedom is experienced by us, that it is sensed, but this is not the truthful
one, because experience would be the one of my personal freedom and Kant wants
to demonstrate that every rational being is free , in order to infer that every
rational being must obey the Categorical Imperative. A second way would be to
show that every rational being has at least the idea of Freedom, i.e. he is
convinced to act according to reason, not only under instincts; he is persuaded
to act in this way, because he sees that acting this way is right, because he is
determined by his reason and not only by blind instincts. But, if a rational
being had the idea of freedom, but were not really free, he would be mistaken
even about his reasonableness; he would think he were acting for some reasons,
whilst he would actually be like a robot. But, as we saw before, being aware of
being rational means being aware of the necessity of acting in accordance with a
law , and what we are trying to do is to justify this necessity.
Surely, if we consider ourselves to be free, we acknowledge ourselves
obliged to follow the moral law, and if we consider ourselves obliged to follow
the moral law is because we think of ourselves as free. But there seems to be a
vicious circle because, until now, it has been demonstrated neither that we are
obliged to follow the law, independently from the conviction of being free, nor
that we are free, independently from the belief of being subject to the law. We
still have to prove that the Categorical Imperative is possible.
There is still a way open to us: ” To inquire whether we do not take one
point of view when ,by means of Freedom, we think of ourselves as a priori
efficient causes, and another point of view when we represent ourselves
reference to our actions as effects which we see before our eyes” [par. 450].
The point of view of Freedom is the one from which we consider ourselves
belonging to the intellectual world. Everyone understands the distinction
between the sensible world and the intellectual world through this criterion:
any object whose existence is given through a modification or a passiveness of
mine, is given just as a phenomenon, that is, how it appears not how it is in
itself. Thus, if something appears, there must be the thing that appears: the
concept of phenomenon presupposes the one of thing in itself. The difference
between appearance and thing in itself correspond to “the difference between
representations which are given to us from without and in which we are passive,
from those which we produce entirely from ourselves and in which we show our own
activity” [par. 451]. This is also the distinction, shown in the “Critics of
Pure Reason”, between intellectus ectypus and intellectus archetypus; the former
receives from the objects a representation and represents them just as they
appear, the latter learns by creating and learning what it has created: it
learns it as it is in itself.
In the Grounding the knowledge that the human being has of himself through
the internal sense does not get him to know what he is in himself . “For since
he does not create himself and since he acquires the concept of himself not a
priori, but empirically, it is natural that he can attain knowledge even about
himself only through inner sense and therefore, only through the appearance of
his nature and the way in which his consciousness is affected. He must
necessarily assume that beyond his own subject’s constitution as composed of
nothing but appearances, there must be something else as basis, namely, his ego
as constituted in itself.” [par.451]. The person finds in himself a faculty that
distinguishes him from all other objects and from himself as affected by objects.
This faculty is Reason, it is pure spontaneity. Now, Determinism is law of the
phenomenal world, therefore, the person, as Reason, as belonging to the
intellectual world, is not affected by the laws of Determinism: he is free. This
is Kant’s proof of Freedom. Is it satisfactory?
Later on, in the “Critics of Practical Reason”, Kant does not attempt to
deduce synthetically Morality from Freedom, as he tried to do in the Grounding
by stating that Freedom was the necessary condition for Morality, but he assumes
the moral law as a “fact of the reason” from which he infers Freedom. There have
been critics blaming Kant of a sort of vicious circle, because he seemed to
demonstrate Freedom by means of deduction from Morality and then to show the
possibility of the Categorical Imperative deducing it from Freedom. Kant answers
that there is no vicious circle because in the ontological order Freedom is the
condition for Morality ( it is not possible to follow the duty for the duty if
you are not free), but in the order of our knowledge, the moral law is the
requirement for Freedom ( we would not consider ourselves free, if we did not
think of ourselves as subject to the moral law). Freedom is the ratio essendi of
the moral law, but the moral law is the ratio cognoscendi of Freedom.
33b