Реферат

Реферат на тему Morality And God Essay Research Paper The

Работа добавлена на сайт bukvasha.net: 2015-06-12

Поможем написать учебную работу

Если у вас возникли сложности с курсовой, контрольной, дипломной, рефератом, отчетом по практике, научно-исследовательской и любой другой работой - мы готовы помочь.

Предоплата всего

от 25%

Подписываем

договор

Выберите тип работы:

Скидка 25% при заказе до 23.11.2024


Morality And God Essay, Research Paper

The belief that morality requires God remains a widely held moral maxim. In particular, it serves as the basic assumption of the Christian fundamentalist’s social theory. Fundamentalists claim that all of society’s troubles – everything from AIDS to out-of-wedlock pregnancies – are the result of a breakdown in morality and that this breakdown is due to a decline in the belief of God. This paper will look at different examples of how a god could be a bad thing and show that humans can create rules and morals all on their own. It will also touch upon the fact that doing good for the wrong reasons can also be a bad thing for the person.

The belief that morality requires God is not limited to theists, however. Many atheists subscribe to it as well. An existentialist once wrote, “If God is dead, everything is permitted.” In other words, if there is no supreme being to lay down the moral law, each individual is free to do as he or she pleases. Without a divine lawgiver, there can be no universal moral law.

The view that God creates the moral law is often called the “Divine Command Theory of Ethics.” According to this view, what makes an action right is that God wills it to be done. That an atheist should find this theory suspect is obvious, for, if one doesn’t believe in God or if one is unsure which God is the true God, being told that one must do as God commands will not help one solve any moral dilemmas. According to Divine Command Theory, nothing is right or wrong unless God makes it so. Whatever God says goes. So if God had decreed that adultery was permissible, then adultery would be permissible.

Let’s take this line of reasoning to its logical conclusion. If the Divine Command Theory were true, then the Ten Commandments could have gone something like this: “Thou shalt kill everyone you dislike. Thou shalt rape every woman you desire. Thou shalt steal everything you desire. Thou shalt torture innocent children in your spare time. …” The reason that this is possible is that killing, raping, stealing, and torturing were not wrong before God made them so. Since God is free to establish whatever set of moral principles he chooses, he could just as well have chosen this set as any other.

However it is absurd to think that such needless killing, raping, stealing, and torturing could be morally permissible. Moreover, to believe that God could have commanded these things is to destroy whatever grounds one might have for praising or worshiping him. And if in accord with the definition of tyrants, justice consists in that which is pleasing to the most powerful? Besides it seems that every act of willing supposes some reason for the willing and this reason, of course, must precede the act.

Leibniz’s position is that, if things are neither right nor wrong independently of God’s will, then God cannot choose one thing over another because it is right. Thus, if he does choose one over another, his choice must be arbitrary. But a being whose decisions are arbitrary is not a being worthy of worship.

The fact that Leibniz rejects the Divine Command Theory is significant, for he is one of the most committed theists in the Western intellectual tradition. He argues at great length that there must be an all-powerful, all-knowing, and all-good God and consequently that this must be the best of all possible worlds, for such a God could create nothing less. What Leibniz demonstrates is that, far from being disrespectful or heretical, the view that morality is independent of God is an eminently sensible and loyal one for a theist to hold.

To avoid the charge of absurdity, a Divine Command theorist might try to deny that the situation described above is possible. He might argue, for example, that God would never condone such killing, raping, stealing, and torturing, for God is all good. But to make such a claim is to render the theory vacuous. The Divine Command Theory is a theory of the nature of morality. It tells us what makes something good by offering a definition of morality. But if goodness is a defining attribute of God, then God cannot be used to define goodness. If being all-good is an essential property of God, then all the Divine Command Theory tells us is that good actions would be willed by a supremely good being. While this is certainly true, it is unenlightening. For it does not tell us what makes something good and hence does not increase our understanding of the nature of morality.

A Divine Command theorist might try to avoid this circularity by denying that goodness is a defining attribute of God. But this would take him from the frying pan into the fire, for if goodness is not an essential property of God, then there is no guarantee that what he wills will be good. Even if God is all-powerful and all-knowing, it does not follow that he is all-good, for, as the story of Satan is supposed to teach us, one can be powerful and intelligent without being good. Thus the Divine Command Theory faces a dilemma: if goodness is a defining attribute of God, the theory is circular, but if it is not a defining attribute, the theory is false. In either case, the Divine Command Theory cannot be considered a viable theory of morality.

The foregoing considerations indicate that it is unreasonable to believe that an action is right because God wills it to be done. One can probably believe that God wills an action to be done because it is right, but to believe this is to believe that the rightness of an action is independent of God. In any event, the view that the moral law requires a divine lawgiver is invalid.

There are those who maintain, however, that even if God is not required as the author of the moral law, he is nevertheless required as the enforcer of it, for without the threat of divine punishment, people will not act morally. But this position is no more plausible than the Divine Command Theory itself.

In the first place, as an empirical hypothesis about the psychology of human beings, it is questionable. There is no explicit evidence that theists are more moral than nontheists. Not only have psychological studies failed to find a significant correlation between frequency of religious worship and moral conduct, but also convicted criminals are much more likely to be theists than atheists.

Second, the threat of divine punishment cannot impose a moral obligation, for might does not make right. Threats force; they do not create a moral duty. If our only reason for obeying God is the fear of punishment if we do not, then, from a moral point of view, God has no more claim to our allegiance than Hitler or Stalin.

Moreover, since self-interest is not an adequate basis for morality, there is reason to believe that heaven and hell cannot perform the regulative function often recognized to them. Heaven is the reward that good people get for being good, and hell is the punishment that bad people get for being bad. But consider this. Good people do good because they want to do good – not because they will personally benefit from it or because someone has forced them to do it. People who do good solely for personal gain or to avoid personal harm are not good people. Someone who saves a drowning child, for example, only because he was offered a reward or was physically threatened does not deserve our praise. If your only reason for performing good actions is your desire to go to heaven or your fear of going to hell – if all your other-regarding actions are motivated purely by self-interest – then you should go to hell because you are not a good person. An obsessive concern with either heaven or hell should actually lessen one’s chances for salvation rather than increase them.

A study was done on infants and their sense of morality. Infants have had not much time to be exposed to moral systems or religion for that matter. The creator of this experiment was Jean Piaget. He looked for a sense of morality when the children were allowed to play with marbles. He found several stages of development among the children, the first being standard behaviors of tasting them, burying them, piling them up, etc. Next, some of these behaviors became ritualized and repeated, as if associated with particular thoughts of the infants performing them. Within two years, small children old enough to speak were making some effort to imitate the rules of the game as practiced by their elders. They did not have the mental equipment yet to remember or understand all these rules. Paradoxically, they considered the rules sacred, yet each child played only against him even when with others, and there was no true competitive play under collective rules. Later, children mastered the rules of marbles in competition with one another. A keen sense of fairness arose that influenced the creation and use of the rules. Finally, though fairness remained paramount, older children came to regard the rules as their collective creation, a contract they form to be able to play with one another.

Thus, the rules evolved to define the conditions for cooperation and the penalties for defection, and may be replaced by other formulations serving the same purpose. To my mind, this research proves conclusively that humans are rules-creating animals and that God is not required as the explanation either of marbles or of morality.

The thought of that terrifies most theists, but it shouldn’t. God wasn’t much help to us in discovering how to cure or prevent smallpox, diphtheria, typhoid, whooping cough, polio, measles, and dozens of other diseases. We had to do it on our own. God wasn’t much help to us in making the scientific discoveries that led to the technology that now makes life so comfortable for us. We had to do it on our own. So if we did all these things without God, surely we can make the moral discoveries that are necessary for society to function in an orderly, beneficial way.

Fundamentalists correctly perceive that universal moral standards are required for the proper functioning of society. But they mistakenly believe that God is the only possible source of such standards. Philosophers as diverse as Plato, Immanuel Kant, and John Rawls have demonstrated that it is possible to have a universal morality without God. Contrary to what the fundamentalists would have us believe, then, what our society really needs is not more religion but a richer notion of the nature of morality.

Bibliography

Louis P. Pojman, Ethical Theory (Belmont,CA: Wadsworth, 1998), 635-637.

Pojman, 646

Robin Le Poidevin, “Are God and Ethics Inseparable or Incompatible”,

*http://hem.passagen.se/nicb/god_ethics.htm* (10 Oct. 1996).

Poidevin, article

Mark I. Vuletic, “Against Moral Argument”,

* http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/mark_vuletic/moral.html* ( 1997).

Mark I. Vuletic, “The Night I Saw the Light”, *http://www.secularhumanism.org/library/fi/allen_wayback.html* ( 11/10/2000).


1. Реферат на тему Industrial Rev Essay Research Paper The Positive
2. Научная работа на тему Фольклорно мифологическая основа повести М Карима Помилование 2
3. Реферат на тему The Milgram Experiment Essay Research Paper The
4. Реферат на тему Yoko Essay Research Paper Thomas Gunn delivers
5. Реферат Регулировка источников питания РЭС
6. Курсовая Деятельность секретаря в приемной руководителя
7. Реферат на тему Kant Essay Research Paper Immanuel Kant was
8. Реферат Особенности применения отдельных форм расчетов в Республике Беларусь
9. Реферат на тему Life Influences In The Writing Of The
10. Статья Части высказывания